I S K O |
Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||
home about ISKO join ISKO Knowledge Organization journal ISKO events ISKO chapters ISKO people ISKO publications Encyclopedia KO literature KO institutions ⇗ KOS registry 🔒 members contact us |
Classificationby Birger Hjørland 1. IntroductionThis article is about classification as a basic term in an interdisciplinary perspective. Classification is a fundamental concept and activity in knowledge organization, but it is also an important concept in many other fields, including biology and philosophy. In knowledge organization and library and information science (LIS), it is mostly about classifying documents, document representations, and concepts (e.g., in thesauri), and library classification systems and ontologies are well-known kinds of knowledge organization systems (KOS). These activities and systems are based on more fundamental conceptions and theories of classifications that are presented in this article. The ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization (IEKO) plans to cover a very broad spectrum of articles related to classification besides the present one. We already have an article about → logical division, and further articles are planned about, for example, library classification, automatic classification, numerical taxonomy, classification of the sciences, classification in specific domains (including biology, physics and chemistry), and much more. This article covers a very complex concept and is therefore highly compressed and abbreviated. In particular, most of the theories mentioned in section 4 deserve to be enlarged on in independent articles that it is hoped will be forthcoming at some point in the future. 2. The meaning of the word classificationAmong the many contributors to the definition of classification two (Frederik Suppe and Henry E. Bliss) are here selected as outstanding. Frederick Suppe distinguished two senses of classification: a broad and a narrow meaning. He called the broad meaning "conceptual classification". Classification is intrinsic to the use of language, hence to most if not all communication. Whenever we use nominative phrases we are classifying the designated subject as being importantly similar to other entities bearing the same designation; that is, we classify them together. Similarly the use of predicative phrases classifies actions or properties as being of a particular kind. We call this conceptual classification, since it refers to the classification involved in conceptualizing our experiences and surroundings" (Suppe 1989, 292). Classification in the narrower meaning Suppe called "systematic classification". A second, narrower sense of classification is the systematic classification involved in the design and utilization of taxonomic schemes such as the biological classification of animals and plants by genus and species (Suppe 1989, 292). Henry E. Bliss (1929) also considered the senses of the word classification and wrote: "[t]his term, like other English derivatives ending in ion, is ambiguously used both in the predicative and in the substantive sense, now for the action and now for the act, sometimes for the process and sometimes for the product" (142). In order to remove this ambiguity, he suggested three definitions proceeding from class as a substantive:
There are many more definitions of classification than the ones given above. For a chronological sample of definitions of classification, see the Appendix. The objects we classify may be physical objects, persons, processes, ideas, concepts, words, etc. Some of these entities, such as concepts, may be both the elements classified and a result of a (new) classification. Table 1: Selected terms used about the units classified and the resulting groups
The objects to be classified have attributes with values. Attributes may, for example, be color or weight. Values may be red or heavy. Classifications are made by considering different attributes and their values. [1] In conclusion: Classification is a term used both about the process to classify (which is a kind of discriminative practice; see Schmidt and Wagner 2004, 392) and about the resulting set of classes, as well as the assignment of elements to pre-established classes. The wide meaning of classification is the process of distinguishing and distribution kinds of "things" into different groups. All narrower meanings of classification are based on the wide definition but add some extra requirements or restrictions put to the classification process and the resulting classification system — for example, the requirement that a classification should use only one criterion of division at a time, that classes should be mutually exclusive, and jointly exhaustive, are requirements demanded by some specific theories of classification, but not requirements that are common for all kinds of classification as here defined. 3. Related terms3.1 Concept/conceptualizationConcept has formerly been defined the following way: Concepts are dynamically constructed and collectively negotiated meanings that classify the world according to interests and theories. Concepts and their development cannot be understood in isolation from the interests and theories that motivated their construction, and, in general, we should expect competing conceptions and concepts to be at play in all domains at all times" (Hjørland 2009, 1522-1523). There is a close relationship — if not total identity — between theories of classification and theories of concept. The class of It is evident that a discussion of classes involves the correlation of classes to concepts, or class-concepts. The class-concept is the mental correlate of the class, the mental basis both of the general idea of the class and of its name, or names (Bliss 1929, 120; italics in original). Spiteri (2008) found that an examination of traditional similarity-based concept theories suggests that they do not provide an adequate account of conceptual coherence. Library and information science needs to explore knowledge-based approaches to concept formation, which suggest that one's knowledge of a concept includes not just a representation of its features, but also an explicit representation of the causal mechanisms that people believe link those features to form a coherent whole. Spiteri (2008) found that rather than representing a universal truth based upon unitary descriptions of concepts, classification systems represent only particular points of view. She hereby supports the argument of Hjørland and Albrechtsen (1999) and Beghtol (2003) that classification research must be situated within specific contexts and the domains in which the classification systems are designed to function, as well as Mai's (2004, 41) claim that "Any classification is relative in the sense that no classification can be argued to be a representation of the true structure of knowledge [...] a classification is merely one particular explanation of the relationships in a given field that satisfies a group of people at a certain point in time". Frické (2012, 33), however, is opposed to considering concepts as mental constructs, and writes that the word concepts "amounts roughly to "general notion" or "general idea" or even "meaning". Many describe concepts as being mental or mental constructions; however, we regard them as abstractions or abstract objects (in the standard Fregean third realm)." In spite of this close connection between classification and concepts, the discourses on concepts and the discourses about classification seem mostly to be separated in the literature. 3.2 CategorizationElin K. Jacob found that classification and categorization are different processes: Although systems of classification and categorization are both mechanisms for establishing order through the grouping of related phenomena, fundamental differences between them influence how that order is effected — differences that do make a difference in the information contexts established by each of these systems. While traditional classification is rigorous in that it mandates that an entity either is or is not a member of a particular class, the process of categorization is flexible and creative and draws nonbinding associations between entities — associations that are based not on a set of predetermined principles but on the simple recognition of similarities that exist across a set of entities. Classification divides a universe of entities into an arbitrary system of mutually exclusive and nonoverlapping classes that are arranged within the conceptual context established by a set of established principles. The fact that neither the context nor the composition of these classes varies is the basis for the stability of reference provided by a system of classification. In contrast, categorization divides the world of experience into groups or categories whose members bear some immediate similarity within a given context. That this context may vary — and with it the composition of the category — is the basis for both the flexibility and the power of cognitive categorization" (Jacob 2004, 527-528). Jacob's distinction is based on the narrow meaning of classification presented in section 2. Her distinction is supported by Schmidt and Wagner (2004), who introduced some distinctions between classification and other forms of discriminatory practice: The point we want to make is that we have to be quite specific in distinguishing different types of discriminative practice: seeing something, seeing something for what it is as opposed to something else (reflecting on what one is seeing), physically separating things in some regular way, saying that x is C ("categorizing" x as C), and classifying x as C according to an inscribed, publicly available classification system. These are radically different practices, involving radically different forms of convention, principles of abstraction, etc. (Schmidt and Wagner 2004, 45-46). About categorization, the same authors wrote: Categorization, by contrast [to seeing and recognizing], is a linguistic operation of ascribing a category or concept to a particular phenomenon by the means of signs. Merely talking about phenomena, however, is not necessarily categorizing them, although talking involves the application of concepts. To categorize is to make a conceptual proposition ("red is a color"). These two sources pose a question about the broad definition of classification mentioned in section 2 of the present article. Nevertheless, this broad definition is widely used in the literature and it will introduce problems to restrict the term classification to the narrow definition. Therefore, the choice made here is to consider classification as synonymous with categorization but to maintain the distinction between classification in a wide and a narrow sense. 3.3 OrderingWordNet 3.1 provides two senses of the noun ordering:
Some authors do not consider historicist classifications (like cladistics systems) as following the concept of classifications: For several centuries all ordering systems were thought to be classifications and the two terms were treated virtually as synonyms. Eventually, however, it was realized that classification means making classes and that ordering systems that are not based on classes, such as sequential listing or cladifications (Mayr 1995), are not classifications. Hence, ordering systems denotes the general concept that includes classification as one of its subdivisions. (Mayr and Bock 2002, 172) Instead, Mayr and Bock suggest that cladistics systems should be considered as ordering systems in a broader category. However, this terminology is not generally used, and it is deviant from the suggestions made in the present article. Ordering depends on conceptual classification but it is broader than systematic classification. Books can be ordered by, for example, by size, language, or publication date, or alphabetically by author or title. For further information about order and ordering systems, see Meinhardt et al. (1984), Mayr (1995), Mayr and Bock (2002) and Schmidt and Wagner (2004). 3.4 TaxonomyThe term taxonomy was first used in 1813 by the French naturalist Augustin-Pyramus de Candolle (Candolle 1813). It became widely used in relation to biological classification but has since spread to other domains. Some authors consider it synonymous with classification, whereas others make distinctions between the two terms. In the following quote, the two terms are considered synonymous: [T]axonomy has acquired a wide range of meanings no longer restricted to the classical understanding of biology. Taxonomy is now applying its early sense of organizing things in accord with particular principles ("taxis": arrangement; "nomos": law) to a broader range of domains after several centuries of limitation to biology and other natural sciences. In the 1990s, taxonomy was redefined as any semantically significant, systematic organization of content or as the process of developing such organization. This definition sometimes includes any collection whose individual elements have been assigned to various nodes of a classification system. Thus, taxonomy is sometimes considered the process of matching collection items with predefined labels, and sometimes it is the creation and arrangement, as well as the resulting product, of the classification system itself (Grove 2010, 5139; references omitted). Hedden (2016) also uses the term taxonomy in a very broad sense, not just about classifications (hierarchical or non-hierarchical) but as a synonym for any kind of knowledge organization system (KOS). However, one may ask, if the term taxonomy is not used with a specific meaning in relation to classification and KOS, why then use it at all? Dahlberg's Classification System for the Literature on Knowledge Organization has class Knowledge classification can be, and often is, TAXONOMIC (sometimes called "entity classification") like the classification of zoology, classification of plants, or classification of chemical elements (which means that they are going to list one concept in one place only in the classification structure). This quote from Slavic is, however, contradicted by other uses of the terminology. Bibliographical classifications may be phenomenon classifications (for example, the system by James Duff Brown (1862-1914); cf. Beghtol 2004; Gnoli 2016) and disciplinary-based library classification systems like the Dewey Decimal Classification (DDC) are also sometimes termed "taxonomies" (see Waltinger et al. 2011). Carl E. Landweh et al. found that a taxonomy is based on a theory. A taxonomy is not simply a neutral structure for categorizing specimens. It implicitly embodies a theory of the universe from which those specimens are drawn. It defines what data are to be recorded and how like and unlike specimens are to be distinguished. In creating a taxonomy of computer program security flaws, we are in this way creating a theory of such flaws, and if we seek answers to particular questions from a collection of flaw instances, we must organize the taxonomy accordingly (Landweh et al. 1994, 214). However, classifications, too, are based on theories (and an atheoretical classification or taxonomy may be considered an oxymoron; see Hjørland 2016b). Therefore, the theoretical basis cannot be used as a criterion for distinguishing classification and taxonomy. Marradi suggested the following distinctions: A taxonomy obtains when several fundamenta divisionis [criteria of division] are considered in succession, rather than simultaneously, by an intensional cl. [classification]. The order in which fundamenta are considered is highly relevant: the taxonomy obtained by using property X to classify a genus and then property Y to classify its species is by no means the same as that obtained by considering property Y first and property X afterwards (Marradi 1990, 146). Marradi suggested the following differences between classifications, typologies, and taxonomies as products:
It is not difficult to find examples of the use of the terms classification, typology, and taxonomy in disagreement with Marradi's definitions. Here, it will not be discussed whether or not it is a good idea to use his definitions prescriptively. 3.5 TypologyTypology is derived from the two Greek words typo meaning "type" and logos meaning "word." The word typology literally means the study of types (subdivisions of particular kinds of things). We saw above (3.4) that according to Marradi (1990) typologies are kinds of classifications in which more than one fundamental criterion of division is simultaneously taken into account. Another definition was provided by Kenneth D. Bailey: Typology is another term for a classification. Two characteristics distinguish typologies from generic classifications. A typology is generally multidimensional and conceptual. Typologies generally are characterized by labels or names in their cells. (Bailey 1994, 4; italics in original) Bailey exemplifies: As a hypothetical example, let us use two dimensions to construct a classification. These dimensions are intelligence (dichotomized as intelligent/unintelligent) and motivation (dichotomized as motivated/unmotivated). Combining these two dimensions creates a fourfold typology; as shown in Table 1.1. These four categories can be defined as cells in the table. In this case, they are types, or type concepts. A motivated and intelligent person can be labeled as successful; an intelligent but unmotivated person is likely to be an underachiever; while a motivated but unintelligent person is an overachiever; and one who lacks both intelligence and motivation is likely doomed to failure. (Bailey 1994, 4; italics in original). A hypothetical fourfold typology (after Bailey 1994, 5; Table 1.1):
The term typology is used in many fields. For example are Carl G. Jung's psychological types famous (Jung 1971). In Library and Information Science (LIS) is typology used, for example about document typologies. Web of Science, for example, distinguishes between article, book review, letter, review, proceeding paper and other types of documents. 4. Theories of classification [2]In this section, the following theories are presented.
4.1 The "classical view" versus "prototype theory" [4]Aristotle developed a theory of classification in which all elements in a given class share at least one characteristic with all other members. Classes should be designed so membership of a class is given by a set of necessary and sufficient characteristics. For example, according to Aristotle's per genus et differentiam definition, man is a rational animal. This definition first considers a class or concept consisting of all animals (including humans). It then claims the essential difference between humans (men) and all other animals is that humans are rational. In this way, the class of In the middle of the twentieth century, a new theory of classification was proposed, which considered itself an alternative to the feature theory that had existed for millennia. Wittgenstein (1953) claimed that not all concepts consist of elements which have a set of necessary or sufficient characteristics. He used the metaphor of family resemblance for a series of overlapping similarities, where no one feature is common to all the elements in the concept. In a family, some members may be alike in one respect (e.g., the shape of the nose) while other members may be alike in other respects. Wittgenstein's famous example is games, where he claimed that no characteristic common to all kind of games exists. Experimental psychologist Eleanor Rosch (1978), inspired by Ludwig Wittgenstein's later philosophy, first defined prototype theory [6]. Given the Roschian theory, some elements are better representatives than others. For example, if the class or concept is bird, in the classical theory this concept may be defined by attributes such as feathers, beak, and the ability to fly, and every bird is as representative as any other. In the prototype theory, on the other hand, a blackbird is considered a good example (at the least by Westerners), while a penguin is considered a bad example. Instead of being defined by necessary or sufficient characteristics, classes are determined by the overall likeness to a prototype — hence the name of the theory. A now well-established division between two theories of concepts and classification is therefore classical or Aristotelian classification on the one side and prototype theory (or polythetic classification) on the other. George Lakoff wrote about these two theories: From the time of Aristotle to the later work of Wittgenstein, categories [and classification] were thought to be well understood and unproblematic. They were assumed to be abstract containers, with things either inside or outside the category. Things were assumed to be in the same category if and only if they had certain properties in common. And the properties they had in common were taken as defining the category. Geoffrey C. Bowker provided another description: An Aristotelian classification works according to a set of binary characteristics, which the object being classified either presents or does not present. At each level of classification, enough binary features are adduced to place any member of a given population into one, and only one class. [...] Aristotelian models [...] have traditionally informed formal classification theory in a broad range of sciences, including biological systematics, geology, and physics. There are still many people subscribing to the classical view, and Wittgenstein's view — and thereby, indirectly, prototype theory — is criticized by Needham (1975), Sutcliffe (1993) and Margolis (1994). See Fox (2011) for a recent discussion of prototype theory in knowledge organization. Thomas Kuhn [8] is well known for his book The structure of scientific revolutions (1962) in which he made the concepts of "scientific paradigm" and "paradigm shift" widespread — including in common language. It is less well known that his later research focused on concepts, classification, and scientific taxonomies and inspired a new theory of concepts called "theory theory". The best introduction to this work is probably that by Andersen et al. (2006), who wrote: According to this theory, the basic conceptual structure of science is a classification system that divides objects into groups according to similarity relations. The grouping is not determined by identifying necessary and sufficient conditions, but by learning to identify similarities and dissimilarities between the objects. It was one of Kuhn's central claims that one learns such concepts by being guided through a series of encounters with objects that highlight the relations of similarity and dissimilarity currently accepted by a particular community of concept users. [...]. The most important aspects of Kuhn's theory are:
A contemporary example: Ornithologists have recently discovered that the blackbird, which so far has been considered one species, should be considered different species which have becoming similar by adapting to the same ecological niche. In the future, we may therefore expect that not just experts, but also amateur ornithologists, schoolchildren, and the rest of us learn to classify birds in a new way. Michael Billig, a social psychologist inspired by rhetoric, proposed another new theory that is probably in harmony with Kuhn's view in important respects. Billig considers that thinking is like a quiet internal argument. Therefore, psychological and rhetorical theories are closely linked, and the psychology of classification/categorization can learn much from rhetoric. Billig (1996) describes modern cognitive psychology's tendency to consider categorization a fundamental cognitive process in both animals and humans. Modern cognitive psychology tends to view "[t]he individual as an active processor of information" in which "the effect of a stimulus depends on how it is categorized and interpreted by the perceiver" (quotations from Eiser 1980, 8). This basic psychological process is often attributed a biological status by cognitive psychologists (this criticism is also raised against Eleanor Rosch). Billig finds that the implication of this view is that humans are tied to prejudiced and bureaucratic modes of thinking. Billig does not consider it wrong that categorization is an important process, but from his studies in rhetoric he argues that there must be two fundamental processes: categorization and particularization, the latter being a reverse process in which something is not just considered an element of a class or a category, but is considered something special. Billig further demonstrates with many examples how humans are able not just to categorize and particularize but also to discuss and consider the way things are categorized. Arguments about categories and particulars are important elements in human communication and thinking, and they are often related to wide-ranging theoretical and ideological issues and conflicts. By including particularization as a basic psychological process, Billig is able to make room for people, who are not just prejudiced and bureaucratic but also open-minded and flexible. In relation to research in knowledge organization, Billig's research raises serious problems for the cognitive view that tries to base classifications on the study of the human mind. The basic lessons from these new theories of classification may be summarized this way:
4.2 The methodology of forming classes, the epistemology of classificationThe fundamental elements of any classification are its theoretical commitments, basic units and the criteria for ordering these basic units into a classification. (Hull 1998) 4.2a Elaine Svenonius (2004) proposed that three epistemological theories are important for knowledge organization (or, as she preferred, knowledge representation):
These views may deserve their own entry in this encyclopedia. They are outlined below. Concerning α, Svenonius raised the criticism that all operational definitions lack validity and that operationalism represents a form of logical positivism. Concerning β, what Svenonius termed "the referential or picture theory of meaning", she found that this, too, "derives from an empiricist view of knowledge" (2004, 574). The author summarized the basic problems with this theory: First, the picture theory assumes a universal form of language in which the meaning of propositions picturing the world are prescribed, relatively fixed, and generally understood. The objection here is that pictures can be differently interpreted. A cup is half full or half empty. A picture of a duck from another viewpoint could be a picture of a rabbit; a picture of a block could be interpreted as a triangular prism. Concerning γ, Svenonius's last theory was the contextual or instrumental theory of meaning. The basic tenet of the instrumental theory of meaning is that we know what a word means when we know how to use it. Svenonius found that this way of thinking led to adoption of the methods of numerical taxonomy. However, numerical taxonomy may be considered a form of empiricism rather than of the contextual or instrumental theory of meaning as developed by pragmatic philosophers. If this understanding is true, we may conclude that Svenonius has not really suggested an alternative to empiricism and logical positivism. Such alternatives are presented below (4.2c). Before this, however, another important view will be presented. 4.2b Alberto Marradi distinguished the following senses of classification as an operation (intellectual and otherwise):
Marradi's two first options are further discussed in the next section. His third option is not related to a new fundamental method and is not further discussed in this article, but this issue is partly dealt with in the entry on Subject. Forthcoming entries on subject analysis, indexing, etc. will also cover this topic. 4.2c Birger Hjørland has suggested that there are four basic theories and approaches to classification [11]: α rationalism; β empiricism; γ historicism, and δ pragmatism/critical theory. All four will be presented and discussed below. The first two (rationalism and empiricism) are related to theories already presented.
4.3 Some metaphysical issues of classification: is there one correct classification?Has the world one unique structure ("taxonomic monism"), or is there more than one structural entity and process ("taxonomic pluralism")? Are the structures of the world mind-independent (realism), or are they artefacts projected into the world (idealism)? Can our classifications be natural, or are they always artificial? These are core issues in the metaphysics of classification. As stated by Anjan Chakravartty: The preeminent question of the metaphysics of classification is that of whether the world is itself naturally subdivided into kinds of things. Are kinds out there, so to speak, or are they rather artefacts of convention, existing only insofar as classificatory practices are brought to bear by creatures such as ourselves? (Chakravartty 2011, 157) We shall here present the following issues: 4.3a Artificial versus natural classification, 4.3b Order versus disorder of things and unity versus disunity of knowledge 4.3a Artificial versus natural classification. Natural classification can be expressed by Plato's metaphor of "carving nature at its joints" (Plato c.370 BC, Phaedrus 265e; see also Campbell et al. 2012). Carl Linnaeus is, however, often recognized as the first scholar to clearly have differentiated "artificial" and "natural" classifications: As far as I can see, Linnaeus was the first to draw a clear terminological distinction between artificial and natural systems, and this was praised as one of his main achievements by later naturalists and philosophers" (Müller-Wille 2007, 550; cf. Müller-Wille 2013, 311). Although Linnaeus considered natural classification the ideal, he recognized that his own system (at least partly) represented an artificial classification. Linnaeus realized that natural orders could not be defined. Even the most "natural", such as the Umbelliferae, the carrot family, lacked features that were unique to and constant within them. Until these were found, natural groups were "like a bell without a clapper"; in modern parlance, they were polythetic (Stevens 1998). However, the meaning of ‘natural classification' has often been considered unclear: In the middle of the seventeenth century, many, like Aristotle 2000 years before, believed in a nature that could be represented as some version of the scala naturae, a linear sequence of organisms arranged according to ideas of "highness" and "lowness", in which man was above all organisms (and often not part of nature), and angels and ultimately god [sic] might be above him. There were many other ways of representing nature, and as the geologist Francis Bather observed in 1927, "not a single naturalist had a clear idea of what he meant by 'natural'. All he knew was that the other fellow's classification was unnatural" (Bather 1927). In early usage, natural history itself for the most part had no historical element; "history" meant "story" or "description" (Stevens 2016, 494). John Stuart Mill suggested the following definition: The Linnæan arrangement answers the purpose of making us think together of all those kinds of plants, which possess the same number of stamens and pistils; but to think of them in that manner is of little use, since we seldom have anything to affirm in common of the plants which have a given number of stamens and pistils (Mill 1872, 498). The ends of scientific classification are best answered, when the objects are formed into groups respecting which a greater number of general propositions can be made, and those propositions more important, than could be made respecting any other groups into which the same things could be distributed [...] Alphabetical arrangement is also a kind of artificial classification because it is not based on relationships between objects, but on formal characteristics of the names of objects. Artificial classifications often serve important but limited practical purposes, whereas natural classifications have broader application functions. (A yet more limited kind of artificial classification is "ad-hoc classification", which is just made for a specific task, non-generalizable, and not intended to be able to be adapted to other purposes: cf. Hudon et al. 2005). Marradi found, however, that use of the term "natural classification" is often connected with a problematic positivist view. [16] William Parry and Edward Hacker explained the concept in accordance with John Stuart Mill's understanding: For example, one may divide rocks — or even animals — into those weighing less than ten grams, those weighing at least ten but less than twenty grams, and so on; but this is likely to be of little use, except perhaps for knowing what it would cost to mail them (Parry and Hacker 1991, 133). Hjørland (2016b) considered the classification of mental disorders in the DSM system. The third edition of this system especially claimed to be atheoretical and tended to give priority to reliability in diagnosis rather than in the validity of classifications. This creates a system with doubtful functions in the understanding and treatment of mental diseases. While it is relatively easy to make a classification reliable (e.g., by classing according to weight, as in Parry and Hacker's quote), it is much more difficult, but also much more important, to make a classification useful for predicting the outcome of interventions. Therefore, the distinction between artificial and natural classification is important when natural is understood as a classification based on a substantial theory — implying that competing theories provide competing natural classifications. There are two additional aspects to consider in relation to natural classification: the concepts of "natural kind" and "naturalism in classification". A natural kind can be understood as a grouping that reflects the structure of the natural world rather than the interests and actions of human beings. Chemical elements — e.g., gold — are often taken as an example of a natural kind. However, the philosophical problems of natural kinds, and how it can be decided if something is or is not a natural kind, are big ones (obviously, the social constructivist denies that natural kinds exist). Here we shall not go further into this issue but leave it to a hopefully forthcoming independent article. There is a large literature on this concept: see, for example, Khalidi (2013). Naturalism in classification may be understood as a general approach to classification theory that establishes a close connection between knowledge organization and classification in empirical science and scholarship (e.g., biological classification, classification of the chemical and physical elements, classification in arts, linguistics, psychiatry, etc.). Naturalism is therefore opposed to the idea that the field of knowledge organization has a set of a priori classification principles or methods. Naturalism in classification is based on the corresponding concept of "naturalistic epistemology", which has been described the following way: Broadly speaking, however, proponents of NE [naturalistic epistemology] take the attitude that there should be a close connection between philosophical investigation — here, of such things as knowledge, justification, rationality, etc. — and empirical ("natural") science (Rysiew 2016). Naturalistic classification is therefore the attempt to learn classificatory principles by studying how the most successful classifications have been constructed in different domains, as well as the discourses and controversies about classification and its philosophy. In the field of knowledge organization, this has been relatively neglected because the field has tended to provide prescriptive principles on how to classify knowledge (e.g., facet analytic principles, standards for thesaurus construction, or user-based methodologies). 4.3b Order versus disorder of things and unity versus disunity of knowledge. It has been (and probably still is) characteristic of many researchers to believe in a fundamental order underlying the apparently confusing empirical picture of the world. Related to this view is a belief in the nature of knowledge to reflect or converge toward this underlying order. The first point is about taxonomic monism versus pluralism; the second is about descriptive monism versus pluralism (or epistemic relativism). Often taxonomic monism is associated with scientific realism, while taxonomic pluralism is associated with relativism. Chakravartty (2011) argued, however, that taxonomic monism is in opposition to contemporary science and that a form of taxonomic pluralism is consistent with realism. Henry Bliss is a library science representative holding the belief in an underlying order of things and in the unity of and consensus of knowledge. He wrote: The more definite the concepts, the relations, and the principles of science, philosophy, and education become, the clearer and more stable the order of the sciences and studies in relation to learning and to life; and so the scientific and educational consensus becomes more dominant and more permanent (Bliss 1933, 37). A critique of this view was made by Satija (1992, 40-41), paraphrasing McGarry (1991, 148): Knowledge is a cultural entity and keeps shifting its pattern like a kaleidoscope. An emergence of the new knowledge modifies the structure of the whole. Contrary to H. E. Bliss (1870-1955) there is no permanent order in knowledge. "Pattern is new every moment", said T.S. Eliot (1888-1965), with a poetic vision. In information science and knowledge organization, this tension between the idea of order and stability and the reality of disorder and relativity is clear in the differences between traditional bibliographical classifications on the one hand, and the bibliometric maps based on, for example, co-citation patterns on the other. Whereas traditional classifications tend to provide relatively stable structures, the citation practices of researchers tend to display very unstable patterns. While the goal of knowledge organization is to discover or construe some kind of order, the nature of the order matters. Francis Miksa, for example, wrote: "In the end, there is strong indication that Ranganathan's use of faceted structure of subjects may well have represented his need to find more order and regularity, in the realm of subjects, than actually exist" (Miksa 1998, 73). This quote may be considered a criticism of Ranganathan in accordance with Hjørland's (2014) criticism of rationalism. Jens-Erik Mai discussed this from the perspective of post- or late modernist philosophy: This paper traces and interrogates the shift from classification-as-ontology, in which everything is defined as it is, to a more contemporary notion of classification-as-epistemology, in which everything is interpreted as it could be — or more precisely, the paper argues for a conceptual move from modern monistic ontology to late-modern pluralistic epistemological foundation for classification theory and practice (Mai 2011, 711). This opens many questions, and the most important claims by Mai may be considered the critique of the positivist view that the researcher and knowledge organizer are neutral agents providing an objective mirror of the universe of knowledge (see also Pando and de Almeida 2016). The same issue was also addressed by philosopher Finn Collin, who discussed a social constructivist view of classification, which he formulated in this way: to isolate a certain kind of thing is the same process as classifying individual things. And classification is a matter of sorting things into groups, the members of which are more similar to each other than to items outside the group. However, things are only similar or dissimilar in certain respects [...]. Classifications are not objective divisions, inherent in the nature of things, but are structures we impose upon nature. [...] kinds of things are indeed human creations (Collin 1993, 29: italics in original). Then Collin wrote (29): "I believe this reasoning is mistaken. What follows from the premises is a less radical conclusion." Later, he summed up his argument: the nominalist argument mistakes a valid anti-essentialist point for an anti-realist one. It is true that there is not, among the true descriptions of a thing, one which is privileged, in the sense that any classification of the thing has to be based upon that particular description. There is no uniquely correct classification of a thing, one that shows what the thing really is, rendering alternative classifications somehow misleading or inappropriate. But it is a mistake to infer from this that things do not in themselves belong to any classifications at all and that things only come to belong to classes when we place them there. Once we relativise similarity and dissimilarity to particular aspects of things, similarity and dissimilarity turn out to be objective, although relational, properties of things, and the predicates that are defined by the equivalency classes of things turn out to be genuine properties of those things. Reality possesses all the properties attributed to it in these alternative descriptions" (Collin 1993, 43; italics in original). An issue regarding Collin's argumentation is "the true descriptions of a thing". Because descriptions are theory-dependent, different descriptions are not necessarily equally true. Also, of course, classifications are made, chosen, or used for a purpose, and therefore our classifications to a large degree will be human creations (but not therefore arbitrary or contingent; within ornithology, for example, there seems now to be considerable optimism that a "final" classification of birds on the overall level seems within reach; cf. Fjeldså 2013). [17] Mazzocchi wrote about the opposite of one right way to "carve nature at its joints", taxonomic pluralism: Ontological pluralist views have also been developed. For instance, Dupré's (1993) "promiscuous realism" conceives the world (his argument refers, above all, to the biological realm) as made up of a multidimensional complexity: things are interconnected and interrelated to one another in multiple ways; there is no unique way of carving nature at its joints or one ultimately right way of classifying or hierarchizing. Rather, there are many equally legitimate ways of dividing the world into "kinds", depending on the purposes of investigations. In this connection, it is worth mentioning the mental models or metaphors that govern our view of how knowledge is organized. The tree model has been historically associated with the philosophical position of classical realism. A number of basic assumptions underlying such a position can be listed. Ontologically, there is: (1) a reality that exists independently of us, (2) a single set of categories, and (3) a single set of essential properties and therefore a unique way of dividing the world into kinds. Epistemologically, saying that also implicitly means that: (4) the ultimate order of the world is within the reach of human cognitive means, i.e. there is an absolute or neutral vantage point from which to grasp reality as it "actually" is, and this vantage point is accessible to us. The tree metaphor is increasingly ousted by alternatives such as net and the rhizome (see Mazzocchi 2013) and it matters which models guide our research and practice. ConclusionThe concept of classification and its associated theories is extremely wide-ranging and interdisciplinary. Many kinds of knowledge must be combined in order to make overall progress in this field. Such projects may be guided by different basic assumptions. Daniel Parrochia seems to base his suggestion for such a program on more formal and mathematical approaches. In 2016 he wrote: In spite of these advances, most of classifications are still based on the evaluation of resemblances between objects that constitute the empirical data. This one is almost always computed by the means of some notion of distance and of some algorithms of aggregation of classes. So all these classifications remain, for technical and epistemological reasons that are detailed below, very unstable ones. A real algebra of classifications, which could explain their properties and the relations existing between them, is lacking. Though the aim of a general theory of classifications is surely a wishful thought, some recent conjecture gives the hope that the existence of a metaclassification (or classification of all classification schemes) is possible (Parrochia 2016). Alternatively, another program may be suggested (not necessarily in conflict with Parrochia's). This program is less formal (and therefore more substantial) and views classifications as tied to (domain) theories. By implication, the study of classification involves the study of theories in different domains and the ontological claims of those theories. The justification of a good classification in this perspective is to make a justification of the theoretical premises on which it is based. AcknowledgementsI am very grateful to Fulvio Mazzocchi, who served as the editor of this article. He and the two anonymous referees provided detailed, knowledgeable, careful, and fruitful suggestions for improving the original manuscript. Also thanks to Daniel Parrochia for positive feedback on the manuscript. Endnotes1. Wesolek (2012, 1) stated: "He [Hjørland] thinks that concept classification should not strive to classify on the basis of the properties of objects, but rather on descriptions of objects that are loosely derived from human activity and social negotiation." In order to classify by properties, we have to know these properties and the argument is that we only know them from descriptions — our own or those of other people (or from perceptions, but such perceptions have to be transferred to descriptions) — and those descriptions or perceptions will be influenced by culture, goals, interests — in short, subjectivity. In this way, classification is always based on properties of objects. Hjørland's definition of classification is, however, correctly cited by Wesolek on the same page: "Classification, as defined by Hjørland, is the 'sorting of objects based on some criteria selected among the properties of the classified objects'." 2. Parrochia and Neuville's (2013) monograph Towards a general theory of classifications is written from the perspective of mathematics but demonstrates surprisingly broad knowledge of classification research, including research in the community of knowledge organization (see also Parrochia 2016). They, too, find that their work is about the epistemology of classifications, not a mathematical textbook or monograph (vii). They write: "[T]he least we can say is that the field of a mathematical theory of classifications is not a completely stable domain, and one is led to think, finally, that a vast side of it is still to be developed. Another reason for the lack of a general theory, close to the previous one, is that scientists are faced with a very difficult problem (finding a formalism enough general to apply to any kind of classifications), for which no complete solution is known at the present. All the same, we think that the research we have carried on for more than thirty years might be of some interest for librarians, logicians, and also for scientists in the different fields of empirical science, all of whom need to devise their own classifications. But this book has a deeper stake. In fact, pure mathematics wants also a general theory of classifications to take over from classic (and too limited) versions of set theory..." (Parrochia and Neuville 2013, xv). Parrochia and Neuville (2013) seem to assume that a general theory of classification(s) must be a mathematical theory, but do not discuss if other views may also be important, or what the relative contribution of mathematics is. No doubt mathematics is important, but it is certainly not all there is to say about classification. 3. An anonymous reviewer wrote: "It is a bit funny to call the methods of forming classes ‘epistemology' (which is theory of knowledge). If anything, it would be 'ontology'." However, the four methodologies suggested in this article are rationalism, empiricism, historicism, and pragmatism, which are well known epistemological positions, and thus normative principles on how to obtain knowledge. It is correct, however, that these positions also rest on different ontological assumptions. The a priori of rationalism is clear ideas or logical units; for empiricism, it is sense impressions; for historicism, it is change; and, for pragmatism, the a priori is living and acting in the world. 4. An anonymous reviewer wrote: "The explanations of the Classical Theory and Prototype Theory are not strong" and provided a helpful, but lengthy improved description. The choice made here is to try to maintain the short outlines here and later to have these theories covered by independent articles. 5. A monothetic class is defined in terms of characteristics that are both necessary and sufficient in order to identify members of that class. This way of defining a class is also termed the Aristotelian definition of a class. A polythetic class is defined in terms of a broad set of criteria that are neither necessary nor sufficient. Each member of the category must possess a certain minimal number of defining characteristics, but none of the features has to be found in each member of the category. This way of defining classes is associated with Wittgenstein's concept of "family resemblances". The monothetic type is a type in which all members are identical in all characteristics; the polythetic type is a type in which all members are similar, but not identical. Bowker (1998, 256) wrote: "Aristotelian models — monothetic or polythetic — have traditionally informed formal classification theory in a broad range of sciences, including biological systematics, geology, and physics". The first part of this quote was eliminated from the same quote in section 4.1 because it seems confusing and probably wrong that polythetic classification is part of formal classification theory and has been termed Aristotelian. 6. The idea is older, however. "The starting point is the work of the great French botanist Michel Adanson, who proposed that a member of a class of plants did not need to possess all the defining features of the class, and that a deviant specimen did not need to be assigned to a separate class (Adanson 1763, i: cliv sqq.) [note omitted]. 'The important point he made was that creatures should be grouped together on the greatest number of features in common, and there is no justification for deciding a priori on the relative importance of characters in making a natural taxonomy' (Sneath 1962: 292)" (Needham 1975, 353). 7. An anonymous reviewer wrote: "Just as a mild correction to Lakoff's verbal flourishes, the Aristotelian-Classical theory certainly had been the subject of major debate, a debate that had lasted 2000 years and involved some of the finest scholars." 8. An anonymous reviewer wrote: "I am not sure about Kuhn and Billig in this setting. We are getting drawn off into potentially quite deep cognitive or social psychology. But isn't our interest storing and retrieving information or knowledge?" Yes, that is our interest, and the claim is that Kuhn and Billig provide important knowledge for this purpose. Kuhn provides the knowledge that we need to consider how different theories or paradigms classify knowledge and relate our decisions to a choice or a negotiation between different views. Billig help us see the problematic assumptions in the cognitive view according to which we have some built-in mechanisms on how to classify knowledge. 9. "From Cesalpino to Linnaeus, this [downward classification by logical division] was the almost universally preferred system, particularly in botany (Mayr 1982, 158-179). In this methodology, the classifier starts with the entire 'universe' — let's say, all animals — and, with the help of divisional logic, divides them into more and more homogeneous groups. A criterion like blood temperature, when applied to animals, results in two groups: warm-blooded and cold-blooded animals. By continuing dichotomy, one finally reaches the species level. Even though Linnaeus in his artificial system still employed downward classification, it had become evident by his time that a reliance on single characters — and the inevitable arbitrariness of the sequence in which these characters were chosen — could lead to rather artificial systems. At the end of the eighteenth century, downward classification was therefore replaced by upward classification. In retrospect, it eventually became evident that the downward procedure actually produces identification schemes rather than classifications. It survives today in the form of keys. Curiously, in the literature of the philosophy of science, particularly of logic, classification by logical division has been considered the method of classification up to modern times" (Mayr 1995, 420-421). 10. "This system [grouping or upwards classification] most closely conveys the basic meaning of the term classification, that is, to assemble items into classes on the basis of resemblance in observed characters" (Mayr 1995, 421) and "After earlier trials by some herbalists and by Magnol, it was particularly Adanson (1763) who promoted classification by grouping. By the first third of the nineteenth century it had become the almost universal method of classifying plants and animals (Mayr 1982, 190-208). The empirical rule guiding the taxonomist was well stated by Whewell (1840, vol. 1, 521): 'The maxim by which all systems professing to be natural must be tested is this: that the arrangement obtained from one set of characters coincides with the arrangement obtained from another set'" (Mayr 1995, 422). 11. An anonymous reviewer wrote: "There wants to be emphasis here that the classification is systematic classification [as opposed to conceptual classification]." However, the suggested principles are meant to serve conceptual classification as well as systematic classification, and a fundamental view is that conceptual classification represents the core theory on which systematic classification is based. The reviewer seems to view the two kinds of classification as too dualistic. 12. Medin and Aguilar (1999, 104; emphasis in original), for example, wrote: "Why is this notion that categories are defined by some "objective" similarity controversial? The main criticism has been that the notion of similarity is too unconstrained to be useful as an explanatory principle (Goodman 1972; Murphy and Medin 1985). Similarity is usually defined in terms of shared properties, but Goodman argued that any two things share an unlimited number of properties (e.g. robins and elephants can move, weight more than two ounces, take up space, can be thought about, etc.). Given this apparent flexibility, it may be that we see things as similar because they belong to the same category and not vice versa. That is, maybe we can explain similarity in terms of categories." 13. About incommensurability, see Kuhn (2000), and consider the following quotes. 14. The following quote exemplifies the complex pattern of different interests that may be at play behind given classifications — in particular in the domain of arts: "The work of DiMaggio (1987) has provided the theoretical foundation for much research on classification systems. His concept of artistic classification systems offers a number of insights. First, the study of classification systems needs to take into account both the consumption and production of art. According to DiMaggio (1987: 441), artistic classification systems consist of 'the way that the work of artists is divided up both in the heads and habits of consumers and by the institutions that bound the production and distribution of separate genres' [italics in original]. On the one hand, classification systems arise out of processes of social distinction, whereby consumers use cultural objects to mark social boundaries. These 'ritual classifications' can thus be influenced by social structural factors at the societal level — such as stratification systems, elite cohesion, social and geographic mobility, etc. — that generate demand for cultural boundaries. On the other hand, classification systems are also influenced and mediated by ‘classification processes' at the production side. DiMaggio (1987) identifies commercial classifications (the classifications used by commercial producers to market their products), administrative classifications (created and enforced by the state), and professional classifications (classifications driven by the incentives of artists to differentiate and mark boundaries). The study of classification systems thus needs to be attentive to the extent to which the categorical demands of consumers and the categories used by producers overlap, diverge, or mutually reinforce each other" (Venrooij and Schmutz 2015, 799). 15. Nobes and Stadler (2013, 575) examine the degree to which classification is determined by who is classifying and they refer to Bloor's (1982, 268) support for the claim of Durkheim and Mauss (1903 [2010]) that the classification of things reproduces a pattern of social arrangements more than a pattern of the things. Durkheim and Mauss found that our classifications necessarily are hierarchical because human social organization, from which our view of nature ultimately flows, is itself hierarchical. This view has been strongly criticized as 'sociologism', but is, as we saw, defended by Bloor (1982). 16. Marradi wrote: "The opposition between "natural" and "artificial" classification is a recurring theme in the last two centuries. Cohen and Nagel have cogently argued that 'any division ... according to some actual trait arbitrarily chosen is perfectly natural... [but it] may also be said to be artificial, in the sense that we select the trait' (1934, 223). Yet, many scholars have continued stressing "naturality" as a desirable property, by gradually re-interpreting it in terms of significant relationships with other classifications (Hempel 1961, version reprinted 1965, 146-7; Kaplan 1964, 50), utility 'for a wider range of inductive generalizations' (Gilmour 1940, 466), 'systematic import' (Huxley 1940; Hempel 1952; Sandri 1969), links with theory (Hempel 1952; Bunge 1967, 83), 'projectibility of discriminating concepts' (Sandri 1969, 99 ff.). In short, the concept of "natural classification" has been transferred from the ontological to the epistemological domain. However, as Tiryakian (1968, 177) has remarked, 'the reification of typologies is a frequent temptation and pitfall'. In a typical manual of the neopositivist period one can still read a statement as plain as 'A natural class is based on the fundamental character of things' (Lenzel 1938, 32). And one may suspect that, if the epistemological coat of paint were scraped off, quite substantial traces of rusty essentialism would loom through the still widespread concern for "natural" classifications" (Marradi 1990, 149). 17. Jon Fjeldså also gave a speech at the University of Copenhagen on 26 March 2014: "Får vi snart en 'endelig' fugleklassifikation?" (Do we soon get a "final" classification of birds?) ReferencesAcademia das Ciências de Lisboa. 2001. Dicionário da língua portuguesa contemporânea. vol. 1. Lisboa: Verbo. Adamson, Robert. 1901. "Classification". In James Mark Baldwin ed., Dictionary of philosophy and psychology. New York, NY: The MacMillan Company, vol. 1, 185. http://psychclassics.yorku.ca/Baldwin/Dictionary/defs/C2defs.htm Adanson, Michel. 1763. Familles des plantes. Paris: Vincent. Adler, Melissa and Joseph T. Tennis. 2013. "Toward a taxonomy of harm in knowledge organization systems". Knowledge Organization 40, no. 4: 266-272. Andersen, Hanne, Peter Barker and Xiang Chen. 1996. "Kuhn's mature philosophy of science and cognitive psychology." Philosophical Psychology 9, no. 3: 347-363. Andersen, Hanne, Peter Barker and Xiang Chen. 2006. The cognitive structure of scientific revolutions. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Aristotle. 350 BCE. Topics. (Translated by William Adair Pickard-Cambridge). Overland Park, KS: Digireads Publishing, 2006. http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/topics.1.i.html Bailey, Kenneth D. (1994). Typologies and taxonomies: An introduction to classification techniques. London: Sage Publications. Bather, Francis Arthur. 1927. "Biological classifications: Past and future". Quarterly Journal of the Geological Society 83 no. 1: 63- 104. Beckner, Morton. 1959. The biological way of thought. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Beghtol, Clare. 2003. "Classification for information retrieval and classification for knowledge discovery: Relationships between 'professional' and 'naïve' classifications". Knowledge Organization 30, no. 2: 64-73. Beghtol, Clare. 2004. "Exploring new approaches to the organization of knowledge: The subject classification of James Duff Brown". Library Trends 52, no. 4: 702-718. Beghtol, Clare. 2010 "Classification theory". In Marcia J. Bates and Mary Niles Maack eds., Encyclopedia of library and information sciences. Third edition. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, vol. 2, 1045-1060. Biggam, Carole Patricia. 2015. The semantics of colour: A historical approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Billig, Michael. 1996. Arguing and thinking: A rhetorical approach to social psychology. Second edition. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Bliss, Henry E. 1929. The organization of knowledge and the system of the sciences. New York, NY: Henry Holt and Company. Bliss, Henry Evelyn. 1933. The organization of knowledge in libraries and the subject-approach to books. New York, NY: H. W. Wilson. Bliss, Henry E. 1935. A system of bibliographical classification. New York: The H. W. Wilson Company. Bloor, David. 1982. "Durkheim and Mauss revisited: Classification and the sociology of knowledge." Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 13, no. 4: 267-297. Bowker, Geoffrey C. 1998. "The kindness of strangers: Kinds and politics in classification systems". Library Trends 47, no. 2: 255-292. Bowker, Geoffrey C. and Susan Leigh Star. 1999. Sorting things out: Classification and its consequences. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Bunge, Mario A. 1967. Scientific research, vol. I: The search for system. New York, NY: Springer. Campbell, Joseph Keim, Michael O'Rourke and Matthew H. Slater eds. 2012. Carving nature at its joints: Natural kinds in metaphysics and science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Candolle, Augustin-Pyramus de. 1813. Théorie élémentaire de la Botanique ou exposition des principes de la classification naturelle et de l'art d'écrire et d'étudier les végétaux. Paris: Deterville. Capecchi, Vittorio and Frank Möller. 1968. "Some applications of entropy to the problems of classification". Quality & Quantity 2, nos. 1-2: 63-84. Carpenter, William Benjamin. 1847. Zoology: A systematic account of the general structure, habits, instincts, and uses of the principal families of the animal kingdom. London: W. S. Orr. Chakravartty, Anjan. 2011. Scientific realism and ontological relativity. The Monist 94, no. 2: 157-180. Chan, Lois Mai. 1994. Cataloging and classification: An introduction. Second edition. New York, NY: McGraw-Hill. Chen, Xiang. 1997. Thomas Kuhn's latest notion of incommensurability. Journal for General Philosophy of Science/Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie 28, no. 2: 257-273. Cohen, Morris Raphael and Ernst Nagel. 1934. An introduction to logic and scientific method. New York, NY: Harcourt. Collin, Finn. 1993. Social constructivism without paradox. Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 28: 24-46. Condorcet, Marie Jean Antoine Nicolas de Caritat, Marquis de. 1777. "Sur les familles naturelles des plantes, et en particulier sur celle des renoncules". Histoire de l'Académie Royale des Sciences (Paris) année 1773: 34-36. Cranz, David. 1767. The history of Greenland: Containing a description of the country and its inhabitants. Vol. I-II. London: The Brethren's Society for the Furtherance of the Gospel among the Heathen. Cutter, Charles Ammi. 1876. Rules for a printed dictionary catalogue. Washington: Government Printing Office. Dahlberg, Ingetraut. 1993. "Knowledge organization: Its scope and possibilities". Knowledge Organization 20, no. 4: 211-222. Dahlberg, Ingetraut. 2010. "International Society for Knowledge Organization (ISKO)". In Marcia J. Bates and Mary Niles Maack eds., Encyclopedia of library and information sciences. Third edition. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, vol. IV: 2941-2949. Darwin, Charles. 1859. On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life. London: J. Murray. DiMaggio, Paul. 1987. Classification in art. American Sociological Review 52, no. 4: 440-455. Dousa, Thomas M. 2009. "Evolutionary order in the classification theories of C. A. Cutter and E. C. Richardson: Its nature and limits". In Proceedings of the 2009 North American Symposium on Knowledge Organization, June 18-19, 2009, Syracuse, New York: 76-90. Published online at: https://journals.lib.washington.edu/index.php/nasko/article/download/12810/11292 Drucker, Donna J. 2014. The classification of sex: Alfred Kinsey and the organization of knowledge. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press. Dupré, John. 1993. The disorder of things: Metaphysical foundations for the disunity of science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dupré, John. 2002. Humans and other animals. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Dupré, John. 2006. "Scientific classification". Theory, Culture & Society 23, nos. 2-3: 30-32. Durkheim, Émile and Marcel Mauss. 1903. "De quelques formes primitives de classification: Contribution à l'étude des représentations collectives". Année Sociologique VI (1901-1902): 1-72. Durkheim, Émile and Marcel Mauss. 2010. Primitive classification. (Translated from the French and with an introduction by Rodney Needham). London: Routledge. Eiser, J. Richard. 1980. Cognitive social psychology. London: McGraw Hill. Faria, Maria Isabel and Maria da Graça Pericão. 2008. Dicionário do livro: Da escrita ao livro electrónico. Coimbra: Almedina. Farradane, Jason E. L. 1950. "A scientific theory of classification and indexing and its practical applications". Journal of Documentation 6, no. 2: 83-99. Farradane, Jason E. L. 1952. "A scientific theory of classification and indexing: Further considerations". Journal of Documentation 8, no. 2: 73-92. Feger, Hubert. 2001. "Classification: Conceptions in the social sciences". In Neil J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes eds., International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 3: 1966-1973. Feger, Hubert. 2015. "Classification: Understandings of in the social sciences". In James D. Wright ed., International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences. Second edition. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 3, 805-810. Fjeldså, Jon. 2013. Avian classification in flux. In Josep del Hoyo, Andrew Elliott, Jordi Sargatal and David A. Christie eds. Handbook of the birds of the world. Special volume 17. Barcelona: Lynx Editions, 77-146. Fox, Melodie J. 2011. "Prototype theory: An alternative concept theory for categorizing sex and gender?" In Richard P. Smiraglia ed., Proceedings from North American Symposium on Knowledge Organization. Toronto, Canada, vol. 3: 151-159. http://journals.lib.washington.edu/index.php/nasko/article/view/12799 Fox, Melodie J. and Hope A. Olson. 2012. "Feminist epistemologies and knowledge organization". In Hur-li Lee and Richard Smiraglia eds., Cultural frames of knowledge. Würzburg: Ergon Verlag, 79-98. Frické, Martin. 2012. Logic and the organization of information. New York, NY: Springer. Frické, Martin. 2016. "Logical division". Knowledge Organization 43, no. 7: 539-549. A version is also available as https://www.isko.org/cyclo/logical_division Galison, Peter and David J. Stump eds. 1996. The disunity of science: Boundaries, contexts, and power. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Gilmour, John Scott Lennox. 1940. "Taxonomy and philosophy", In Julian Huxley ed., The new systematics. Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 461-474. Gitelman, Lisa ed. 2013. 'Raw data' is an oxymoron. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Gnoli, Claudio. 2006. "Phylogenetic classification". Knowledge Organization 33, no. 3: 138-152. Gnoli, Claudio. 2016. "Classifying phenomena, part 1: Dimensions". Knowledge Organization 43, no. 6: 403-415. Goodman, Nelson. 1972. Seven strictures on similarity. In Nelson Goodman ed., Problems and projects. New York, NY: Bobbs-Merrill, 437-446. Grove, Andrew. 2010. "Taxonomy". In Marcia J. Bates and Mary Niles Maack eds., Encyclopedia of library and information sciences. Third edition. Boca Raton, FL: CRC Press, vol. VII: 5139-5148. Hedden, Heather. 2016. Accidental taxonomist. Second edition. Medford, NJ: Information Today. Hempel, Carl Gustav. 1952. Fundamentals of concept formation in empirical science. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press. Hempel, Carl Gustav. 1961. "Fundamentals of taxonomy". In Joseph Zubin ed., Field studies in mental disorders. New York, NY: Grune & Stratton. (Quotations from the version are reprinted in Carl G. Hempel, Aspects of scientific explanation and other essays in the philosophy of science. Glencoe, IL: Free Press, 1965, 137-154). Hennig, Willi. 1966. Phylogenetic systematics. (Translated by D. Dwight Davis and Rainer Zangerl). Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press. Henry, Devin. 2011. "Aristotle's pluralistic realism". The Monist 94 no. 2: 197-220. Hjørland, Birger. 2003. "Fundamentals of knowledge organization". Knowledge Organization 30 no. 2: 87-111. Hjørland, Birger. 2009. "Concept theory". Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 60, no. 8: 1519-1536. Hjørland, Birger. 2011. "The importance of theories of knowledge: Indexing and information retrieval as an example". Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 62, no. 1: 72-77. Hjørland, Birger. 2013. "Citation analysis: A social and dynamic approach to knowledge organization". Information Processing and Management 49, no. 6: 1313-1325. Hjørland, Birger. 2014. "Is facet analysis based on rationalism? A discussion of Satija (1992), Tennis (2008), Herre (2013), Mazzocchi (2013b), and Dousa and Ibekwe-SanJuan (2014)". Knowledge Organization 41, no. 5: 369-376. Hjørland, Birger. 2015. "Are relations in thesauri 'context free, definitional, and true in all possible worlds'"? Journal of the Association for Information Science and Technology 66, no. 7: 1367-1373. Hjørland, Birger. 2016a. "Informetrics needs a foundation in the theory of science." In Cassidy Sugimoto ed., Theories of informetrics and scholarly communication. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter, 20-46. Hjørland, Birger. 2016b. "The paradox of atheoretical classification". Knowledge Organization 43, no. 5: 313-323. Hjørland, Birger and Hanne Albrechtsen. 1999. "An analysis of some trends in classification research". Knowledge Organization 27, no. 1: 131-139. Hjørland, Birger and Karsten Nissen Pedersen. 2005. "A substantive theory of classification for information retrieval". Journal of Documentation 61, no. 5: 582-597. Hudon, Michéle, Sabine Mas and Dominique Gazo. 2005. "Structure, logic, and semantics in ad hoc classification schemes applied to web-based libraries in the field of education. Canadian Journal of Information and Library Science/La Revue canadienne des sciences de l'information et de bibliothéconomie 29, no. 3: 265-288. Hull, David L. 1998. "Taxonomy". In Edward Craig ed., Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy. London: Routledge, vol. 9, 272-276. Huxley, Julian ed. 1940. The new systematics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Huxley, Thomas Henry. 1869. An introduction to the classification of animals. London: John Churchill & Sons. https://archive.org/stream/anintroductiont00huxlgoog#page/n4/mode/2up ISO 5127-6. 1988. Documentation et information — Vocabulaire: Partie 6: Langages documentaires. In Documentation et information: Recueil de normes ISO I. Genève: ISO, 87-111. Jacob, Elin K. 2004. "Classification and categorization: A difference that makes a difference". Library Trends 52, no. 3: 515-540. Jung, Carl G. (1971). The collected works of C. G. Jung. Volume 6: Psychological types. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Kaplan, Abraham. 1964. The conduct of inquiry. San Francisco, CA: Chandler. Kedrow, Bonifatii Mikhailovich. 1975. Klassifizierung der Wissenschaften 1-2. Moskau: Verlag Progress. Khalidi, Muhammad Ali. 2013. Natural categories and human kinds: Classification in the natural and social sciences. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press. Klaus, Georg. 1976. "Klassifikation". In Georg Klaus and Manfred Buhr eds., Philosophisches Wörterbuch Band 1-2. 12. Aufl. Leipzig: Bibliographisches Institut, vol. 1: 628-629. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The structure of scientific revolutions. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1974. "Second thoughts on paradigms". In Frederick Suppe ed., The structure of scientific theories. Urbana, IL: University of Illinois Press, 459-482. (Reprinted in Thomas S. Kuhn. 1977. The essential tension. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 293-319). Kuhn, Thomas S. 2000. The road since structure: Philosophical essays, 1970-1993. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Lakoff, George. 1987. Women, fire and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Lancaster, F. Wilfrid. 1998. Indexing and abstracting in theory and practice. Second edition. London: Library Association. Landweh, Carl E., Alan R. Bull, John P. McDermott and William S. Choi. 1994. "A taxonomy of computer program security flaws". ACM Computing Surveys 26, no. 3: 211-254. Lenzel, Victor F. 1938. "Procedures of empirical science". In Otto Neurath, Rudolf Carnap and Charles W. Morris eds., International encyclopedia of unified science. Chicago, IL: Chicago University Press, vol. I, no. 5. Linnaeus, Carl. 1767. Fundamenta entomologiæ. Uppsala: John Edman. https://web.archive.org/web/ 20070713235756/http://huntbot.andrew.cmu.edu/HIBD-PDF/LinnaeanDiss/Liden-154.pdf McGarry, Kevin. 1991. "Epilogue: Differing views of knowledge". In Arthur Jack Meadows ed., Knowledge and communication: Essays on the information chain. London: Library Association, 132-152. Mai, Jens Erik. 2004. "Classification in context: Relativity, reality, and representation". Knowledge Organization 31, no. 1: 39-48. Mai, Jens Erik. 2011. "The modernity of classification". Journal of Documentation 67, no. 4: 710-730. Margolis, Eric. 1994. "A reassessment of the shift from the classical theory of concepts to prototype theory". Cognition 51, no. 1: 73-89. Marradi, Alberto. 1990. "Classification, typology, taxonomy". Quality and Quantity 24, no. 2: 129-157. Prepublication [not identical] available at: http://web.archive.org/web/20040705070709/http://www.unibo.edu.ar/marradi/classqq.pdf May, Ronald W. 1982. "Discriminant analysis in cluster analysis". In Herschel C. Hudson ed., Classifying social data. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass, 39-55. Mayr, Ernst. 1982. The growth of biological thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Mayr, Ernst. 1995. Systems of ordering data. Biology and Philosophy 10, no. 4: 419-434. Mayr, Ernst and Walter Joseph Bock. 2002. "Classifications and other ordering systems." Journal of Zoological Systematics and Evolutionary Research 40, no. 4: 169-194. Mazzocchi, Fulvio. 2013. "Images of thought and their relation to classification: The tree and the net". Knowledge Organization 40, no. 6: 366-374. Mazzocchi, Fulvio. 2017. "Relations in KOS: Is it possible to couple a common nature with different roles?" Journal of Documentation 73, no. 2: 368-383. McKenna, Malcolm C. and Susan K. Bell. 1998. Classification of mammals above the species level. New York, NY: Columbia University Press. Medin, Douglas L. and Cynthia Aguilar. 1999. "Categorization". In Robert A. Wilson and Frank C. Keil eds., The MIT encyclopedia of the cognitive sciences. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 104-106. Meinhardt, Helmuth et al. 1984. "Ordnung". In Joachim Ritter and Karlfried Gründer eds., Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Band 6, 1249-1310. (Meinhardt, Helmut, "Ordnung I Antike", 1251-1254; Hübener, Wolfgang, "Ordnung II Mittelalter", 1254-1279; Dierse, Ulrich, "Ordnung III Neuzeit", 1280-1303; Steiner, Hans-Georg, "Ordnung IV Mathematik Logik", 1303-1309; Sauer, Werner, "Ordnung der Begriffe", 1309-1310). Miksa, Francis L. 1994. "Classification". In Wayne A. Wiegand and Donald G. Davis eds., Encyclopedia of library history. New York, NY: Garland Publishing, 144-153. Miksa, Francis L. 1998. The DDC, the universe of knowledge, and the post-modern library. Albany, NY: Forest Press. Mill, John Stuart. 1843. A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation. London: John W. Parker, West Strand. Mill, John Stuart. 1872. A system of logic, ratiocinative and inductive: Being a connected view of the principles of evidence and the methods of scientific investigation vol. 1-2. Eighth edition. London: Longmans, Green, Reader, and Dyer. http://www.archive.org/download/systemoflogicrat00milluoft/systemoflogicrat00milluoft.pdf Moss, Wilfred Raymond. 1964. "Categories and relations: Origins of two classification theories". American Documentation 15, no. 4: 296-301. Müller-Wille, Staffan. 2007. "Collection and collation: Theory and practice of Linnaean botany". Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 38, no. 3: 541-562. Müller-Wille, Staffan. 2013. "Systems and how Linnaeus looked at them in retrospect". Annals of Science 3: 305-317. Murphy, Gregory L. and Douglas L. Medin. 1985. "The role of theories in conceptual coherence". Psychological Review 92, no. 3: 289-316. Needham, Rodney. 1975. "Polythetic classification: Convergence and consequences". Man. New Series 10, no. 3: 349-369. Nobes, Christopher and Christian Stadler. 2013. How arbitrary are international accounting classifications? Lessons from centuries of classifying in many disciplines, and experiments with IFRS data. Accounting Organizations and Society 38, no. 8: 573-595. OED Online. 1990. Oxford English dictionary: the definitive record of the English language. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. Padian, Kevin. 1999. "Charles Darwin's views of classification in theory and practice". Systematic Biology 48, no. 2: 352-364. Pando, Daniel Abraao and Carlos Candido de Almeida. 2016. "Knowledge organization in the context of postmodernity from the theory of classification perspective". Knowledge Organization 43, no.2: 113-117. Parrochia, Daniel 2016. "Classification". In James Fieser and Bradley Dowden eds., The Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. Martin, TN: University of Tennessee at Martin. http://www.iep.utm.edu/classifi/ Parrochia, Daniel and Pierre Neuville. 2013. Towards a general theory of classifications. Bäsel: Birkhaüser. Parry, William T. and Edward A. Hacker. 1991. Aristotelian logic. New York, NY: State University of New York Press. Pihlström, Sami. 2009. Pragmatist metaphysics: An essay on the ethical grounds of ontology. New York, NY: Continuum. Plato. c.370 BC. Phaedrus. (Translated by Alexander Nehamas and Paul Woodruff eds.). Cambridge, MA: Hackett Publishing Co, Inc., 1995. Popper, Karl Raimund. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson. http://strangebeautiful.com/other-texts/popper-logic-scientific-discovery.pdf Ranganathan, Shiyali Ramamrita. 1967. Prolegomena to library classification. Third edition. London: Asia Publishing House. Reid, Thomas. 1785. "Abstraction". Reprinted in James F. Bennett ed. 1855. Essays on the intellectual powers of man by Thomas Reid. Sixth edition (redacted text). Boston, MA: Phillips, Sampson, and Company, 298-330. https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=hvd.hwaili;view=1up;seq=17 Richardson, Ernest Cushing. 1901. Classification, theoretical and practical: Vol. I: The order of the sciences; vol. II: The classification of books. New York, NY: Charles Scribner's Sons. https://babel.hathitrust.org/cgi/pt?id=uiug.30112049904011;view=1up;seq=17 Rijsbergen, Cornelis Joost van. 1979. Information retrieval. Second edition. London: Butterworths. Ritter, Joacim, Karlfried Gründer and Gabriel Gottfried eds. 1971-2007. Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie Bd. 1-13. Basel: Schwabe & Co. Rosch, Eleanor. 1978. "Principles of categorization". In Eleanor Rosch and Barbara Bloom Lloyd eds., Cognition and categorization. Hillsdale, NJ: L. Erlbaum Associates, 27-48. Rysiew, Patrick. 2016. "Naturalism in epistemology". In Edward N. Zalta ed., The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. Spring 2016 edition. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/epistemology-naturalized/ Sandri, Giorgio. 1969. "On the logic of classification", Quality & Quantity 3, nos. 1-2: 80-124. Sankey, Howard. 1998. Taxonomic incommensurability. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 12, no. 1: 7-16. Satija, Mohinder P. 1992. Book review of Meadows (1991): Knowledge and communication: Essays on the information chain. International Classification 19, no. 1: 39-41. Satija, Mohinder P. 2000. "Library classification: An essay in terminology. Knowledge Organization 27, no. 4: 221-229. Schmidt, Kjeld and Ina Wagner. 2004. "Ordering systems. Coordinative practices and artifacts in architectural design and planning". The Journal of Collaborative Computing 13, nos. 5-6: 349-408. Shera, Jesse H. 1965. Libraries and the organization of knowledge. Hamden, CT: Archon Books. Simôes, Maria da Graça, M. Cristina V. de Freitas and Blanca Rodríguez-Bravo. 2016. "Theory of classification and classification in libraries and archives: Convergences and divergences". Knowledge Organization 43 no. 7: 530-538. Slavic, Aida. 2000. A definition of thesauri and classification as indexing tools: A DCMI note. http://dublin core.org/documents/2000/11/28/thesauri-definition/ Sloan, Phillip R. 1981. "Classification". In William F. Bynum, E. Janet Browne and Roy Porter eds., Dictionary of the history of science. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 68-71. Sneath, Peter Henry Andrews. 1962. "The construction of taxonomic groups". In Geoffrey Clough Ainsworth and Peter Henry Andrews Sneath eds., Microbial classification. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 289-332. Soergel, Dagobert. 2004. "Information organization". In William Sims Bainbridge ed., Berkshire encyclopedia of human-computer interaction. Great Barrington, MA: Berkshire Publishing Group LLC, vol. 1, 355-360. Sokal, Robert R. and Peter H. A. Sneath. 1963. Principles of numeric taxonomy. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman. Spiteri, Louise F. 2008. "Concept theory and the role of conceptual coherence in assessments of similarity". Proceedings of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 45, no. 1: 1-12. Stevens, Peter F. 1998. "Linnaeus, Carl von (1707-78) ". In Edward Craig ed., Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy, version 1.0. London: Routledge. (Electronic source, no pages). DOI: 10.4324/9780415249126-Q059-1 Stevens, Peter F. 2016. "Schools of classification". In Richard M. Kliman ed., Encyclopedia of evolutionary biology. San Diego, CA: California Academic Press, vol. 3, 494-498. Suppe, Frederick. 1989. "Classification". In Erik Barnouw ed., International encyclopedia of communications. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, vol. 1, 292-296. Sutcliffe, John Philip. 1993. "Concept, class, and category in the tradition of Aristotle". In Iven van Mechelen, James Hampton, Ryszard S. Michalski and Peter Theuns eds., Categories and concepts. London: Academic Press, 35-65. Svenonius, Elaine. 2000. The intellectual foundation of information organization. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. Svenonius, Elaine. 2004. "The epistemological foundations of knowledge representations". Library Trends 52, no. 3: 571-587. Taylor, Arlene G. 1999. The organization of information. Englewood, CO: Libraries Unlimited, Inc. Tiryakian, Edward A. 1968. "Typologies". In David L. Sills ed., International encyclopedia of the social sciences. New York, NY: Macmillan, vol. 16, 177-185. Veloso, Adriano and Wagner Meira Jr. 2011. Demand-driven associative classification. London: Springer. Venrooij, Alex van and Vaughn Schmutz. 2015. "Classifications in popular music". In James D. Wright ed., International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral science. Second edition. Amsterdam: Elsevier, vol. 3, 799-804. Venter, J. Craig, Karin Remington, John F. Heidelberg, Aaron L. Halpern, et al. 2004. "Environmental genome shotgun sequencing of the Sargasso Sea". Science 304 no. 5667: 66-74. Waltinger, Ulli, Alexander Mehler, Mathias Lösch and Wolfram Horstmann. 2011. "Hierarchical classification of OAI metadata using the DDC taxonomy". In Raffaella Bernardi, Frederique Segond and Ilya Zaihrayeu eds., Advanced language technologies for digital libraries. International Workshops on NLP4DL 2009, Viareggio, Italy, June 15, 2009 and AT4DL 2009, Trento, Italy, September 8, 2009. Heidelberg: Springer, 29-40. (Volume 6699 of Lecture Notes in Computer Science). Wesolek, Andrew. 2012. "Wittgensteinian support for domain analysis in classification". Library Philosophy and Practice (e-journal), paper 795. http://digitalcommons.unl.edu/libphilprac/795 Whewell, William. 1840. The philosophy of the inductive sciences: Founded upon their history. London: J.W. Parker, vol. 1-2. Wilkins, John S. 2013. "Biological essentialism and the tidal change of natural kinds". Science and Education 22, no 2: 221-240. http://philpapers.org/rec/WILBEA Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Oxford, UK: Basil Blackwell. WordNet 3.1. "Classification". http://wordnetweb.princeton.edu/perl/webwn?s=classification Appendix: A sample of definitions of classification (chronological)The intention is to provide a comprehensive list of definitions of classification, and the idea is to update the list when new definitions are discovered in the literature. The sources for such definitions are surprisingly few and meager. The Oxford English dictionary provides a number of quotes back to 1767 but misses important ones such as Darwin (1859) and Huxley (1869) (see also below under 2010). Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie Bd. 1-13 (edited by Joachim Ritter) has no article "Klassifikation" or "Taxonomie" (but does have on, for example, "Kategorie, Kategorienlehre", "Ordnung" and "System, Systematik, Systematisch"). McKenna and Bell (1998, 11-33) provide an overview of the history and theory of classification and state: "The word 'classification' was not part of the scientific literature until the last decades of the eighteenth century. The first use of which we are aware occurs in a botanical paper by the Marquis de Condorcet (1777: 35)". However, earlier uses are listed below. Plato (c.370 BC) Aristotle (350 BCE) Michel Adanson (1763, clvi) David Cranz (1767, vol. 1, ix) Carl Linnaeus (1767, 152) Thomas Reid (1785, 191) William Whewell (1840, vol. 1, xxxiii, XCV) John Stuart Mill (1843, vol. 2, Bk. IV, Ch. 7, 299-300) William Benjamin Carpenter (1847, I. §2) Charles Darwin (1859, 420) Thomas Henry Huxley (1869, 1) Charles Ammi Cutter (1876, 10) Robert Adamson (1901, vol. 1, 185) Ernest Cushing Richardson (1901, 1) Henry E. Bliss (1935, 3) Jason E. L. Farradane (1950, 83). Jason E. L. Farradane (1950, 87). Jason E. L. Farradane (1952, 73-74). Jesse H. Shera (1965, 120) Jesse H. Shera (1965, 127) Shiyali Ramamrita Ranganathan (1967, Chapter CP, 77-78)
Classification in Sense 3 is usually practised by large business concerns having to handle a large number of commodities. The Customs Authorities too use Classification in Sense 3 in their published list of commodities liable to customs duty. 4. Classification in Sense 3 when complete assortment is made of an amplified universe — that is, when the entities and the pseudo-entities arising in the process of successive assortment stand arranged in one filiatory sequence, each with its Class Number. (See Chap CH and CK). Classification in Sense 4 is not used very much. It is only classification in Sense 3 and Sense 5 that are frequently in demand. 5. Classification in Sense 4 with all the entities removed but only the pseudo-entities or classes retained — each class having the number representing it. (See Chap CM). It is classification in Sense 5 that is used,
It should be recalled that that in classification in Sense 5
Bonifatii Mikhailovich Kedrow (1975, vol. 1, 3) Georg Klaus (1976, 628-629) Phillip R. Sloan (1981, 68) ISO 5127-6 (1988, 93) Lois Mai Chan (1994, 259) Francis L. Miksa (1994, 144) Frederick Wilfrid Lancaster (1998, 17) Geoffrey Bowker and Susan Leigh Star (1999, 10) Arlene G. Taylor (1999, 237) Satija (2000, 222) Elaine Svenonius (2000, 10) Hubert Feger (2001, 1966) The Portuguese Language Dictionary of the Academy of Sciences (Academia das Ciências de Lisboa 2001, 837). Ernst Mayr and Walter Joseph Bock (2002) Kjeld Schmidt and Ina Wagner (2004, 392) Dagobert Soergel (2004, 358) Faria and Pericão (2008, 258) Clare Beghtol (2010, 1045) Ingetraut Dahlberg (2010, 2941)
Oxford English Dictionary (update from 2010)
Adriano Veloso and Wagner Meira (2011, 9) Daniel Parrochia and Pierre Neuville (2013, 21) WordNet (3.1) [downloaded 2016-05-21] defines four senses of the noun 'classification' of which three are relevant for this entry:
Version 1.2 (= Version 1.1 plus references to Dahlberg 1993 and Gnoli 2016 and minor corrections); Published 2017-02-23; Article category: Core concepts This article (version 1.0) is published in Knowledge Organization 44, no. 2: 97-128. ©2017 ISKO. All rights reserved. |
||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||||