I S K O

 

Knowledge pyramid
The DIKW hierarchy

by Martin Frické

Table of contents:
1. Introduction
2. What is the core account of DIKW?
3. Background concepts
    3.1 Data
    3.2 Information
    3.3 Knowledge
    3.4 Wisdom
4. Modern developments, variations, and rebuttals of DIKW
5. Drawing it all together
    5.1 Logico-conceptual point of view: 5.1.1 Data to information; 5.1.2 Information to knowledge; 5.1.3. Knowledge to wisdom
    5.2 DIKW in the setting of work processes
6. Conclusion
Acknowledgement
Endnotes
References
Colophon

Abstract:
The data-information-knowledge-wisdom (DIKW) hierarchy or pyramid is a model or construct that has been used widely within information science and knowledge management. The nature of the pyramid is explained, and its historical origin is described. The conceptual components of the pyramid — i.e. data, information, knowledge, and wisdom — are given brief explication. Some modern developments, criticisms, and rebuttals of the DIKW Pyramid are described. Nowadays, the DIKW Pyramid would generally be considered to be unsatisfactory. The arguments and reasoning behind this conclusion are sketched. It is claimed that two more concepts: document and sign are necessary to provide a fruitful theoretical frame for knowledge organization.

1. Introduction

Seeing information in terms of a data-information-knowledge-wisdom (DIKW) hierarchy or pyramid is commonplace (Bates 2005; Frické 2009; Rowley 2007; Zins 2007; Baskarada and Koronios 2013).

Figure 1: The Knowledge Pyramid (Wikimedia Commons, by Longlivetheux, CC-BY-SA)

As Rowley writes

The hierarchy referred to variously as the ‘Knowledge Hierarchy’, the ‘Information Hierarchy’ and the ‘Knowledge Pyramid’ is one of the fundamental, widely recognized and ‘taken-for-granted’ models in the information and knowledge literatures. It is often quoted, or used implicitly, in definitions of data, information and knowledge in the information management, information systems and knowledge management literatures (Rowley 2007, 163)

Rowley (2007) offers a detailed exegesis of just how widespread this view is, and of the similarities and differences between the writers’ statements. There also have been wide-ranging discussions on the JESSE listserv (Wallace 2005) and on the Knowledge Management for Development Wiki (KM4DEV 2012). Further, Zins (2007) has surveyed forty five leading researchers on the topic and produced 130 definitions of data, information, and knowledge.

One issue that arises immediately is that there is not a single concept of information, nor, for that matter, a single concept of data, or of knowledge. Floridi (2011) describes the concepts of information as forming an archipelago; we might say that the concepts of data and the concepts of knowledge also form archipelagos. It is unclear whether the fourth concept, the concept of wisdom is single or many; the uncertainty here is primarily because, comparatively speaking, there has been nowhere near as much research and analysis on wisdom as there has on the other three families of concepts.

This plethora suggests that it would be prudent to focus on a core of the different accounts. Also, the present article has as its topic "The Knowledge Pyramid". Certainly, the component concepts of that pyramid are of interest in themselves — indeed, data, information, and knowledge have encyclopedia entries of their own elsewhere [1] — but here it is the relationships between the concepts that are central.

Historically, the strands leading to DIKW come from a mention by the poet T.S. Eliot [2] and, separately, from research from Harland Cleveland and the systems theorists Adler, Ackoff and Zeleny (Rowley 2007; Sharma 2008; Cleveland 1982; Lambe 2011; Williams 2014). The main views are perhaps best expressed in the traditional sources of Adler (1986), Ackoff (1989) and Zeleny (1987).

There is another preliminary issue. DIKW arises in two separate contexts: managing information in business process settings, and discussing data, information etc. as logico-conceptual constructs demanding analysis and explication. The former is certainly important as a real world practical challenge, and models, including DIKW and its variations, have a central role to play (Bedford and Lewis 2015; Duffield and Whitty 2015; Roberts 2015; Williams 2014). The latter context is more the province of theoretical researchers in library and information science (Dinneen and Brauner 2015; Van der Veer Martens 2015; Yu 2015).

The present article tends to be logico-conceptual in its approach (although some lead-in citations are given to the business process literature).

[top of entry]

2. What is the core account of DIKW?

What, at the heart, is DIKW and how does it work? It is suggested that there is a hierarchy built on the foundation of data. Ackoff (1989) explains it top down:

Wisdom is located at the top of a hierarchy of types …. Descending from wisdom there are understanding, knowledge, information, and, at the bottom, data. Each of these includes the categories that fall below it (Ackoff 1989, 3)

Ackoff includes a fifth level, “understanding”; typically, that is not done (but see Bawden and Robinson 2015).

It is supposed that the many and various items of the world have properties that can be observed. And data is the symbolic representation of these observable properties (Rowley 2007, Section 5.2 "Defining Data"). The prime example of data and data acquisition is provided by automatic instrument systems; an unmanned weather station, for instance, may record daily maximum and minimum temperatures; such recordings are data. Ackoff writes

Data are symbols that represent properties of objects, events and their environments. They are products of observation. To observe is to sense. The technology of sensing, instrumentation, is, of course, highly developed (Ackoff 1989, 3).

Next up the hierarchy is information. This is relevant, or usable, or significant, or meaningful, or processed, data (Rowley 2007, Section 5.3 "Defining Information"). The vision is that of a human asking a question beginning with, perhaps, “who”, “what”, “where”, “when”, or “how many” (Ackoff 1989, 3); and the data is processed into an answer to an enquiry. When this happens, the data becomes “information”. Data itself is of no value until it is transformed into a relevant form. In consequence, the difference between data and information is functional, not structural (Ackoff 1989, 3).

Information can also be inferred from data — it does not have to be immediately available. For example, were an enquiry to be “what is the average temperature for July?”; there may be individual temperatures explicitly recorded as data, but perhaps not the average temperature; however, the average temperature can be calculated or inferred from the data about individual temperatures. The processing of data to produce information often reduces that data (because, typically, only some of the data is relevant). Ackoff writes

Information systems generate, store, retrieve, and process data. In many cases their processing is statistical or arithmetical. In either case, information is inferred from data. (Ackoff 1989, 3)

Information is relevant data, together with, on occasions, the results of inferences from that relevant data. Information is thus a subset of the data, or a subset of the data augmented by additional items inferred or calculated or refined from that subset.

The next category is knowledge. Users of this hierarchy often construe knowledge as know-how, or skill, rather than knowledge in the sense of the know-that of propositional knowledge. Ackoff suggests that know-how allows an agent to promote information to a controlling role — to transform information into instructions.

Knowledge is know-how, for example, how a system works. It is what makes possible the transformation of information into instructions. It makes control of a system possible. To control a system is to make it work efficiently. (Ackoff 1989, 4)

Further up the hierarchy comes wisdom — a category that seems always to have been given only limited discussion (but see Dalal 2012; Hoppe et al. 2011; Liew 2013). While wisdom is traditionally taken to be a layer in the hierarchy, few authors discuss it or use it. This may be because it is not required for the problems they address (Rowley 2007).

Ackoff, while not really defining wisdom, does explain how it works:

Wisdom adds value, which requires the mental function we call judgement. […] The value of an act is never independent of the actor [… ethical and aesthetic values] are unique and personal.
[…] wisdom-generating systems are ones that man will never be able to assign to automata. It may well be that wisdom, which is essential to the effective pursuit of ideals, and the pursuit of ideals itself, are the characteristics that differentiate man from machines. (Ackoff 1989, 9)

An important point is being made here. In some sense or other, the three lower layers of the DIKW pyramid can, or might, be recorded and manipulated by computers. However, in Ackoff’s view, wisdom requires a human actor, and that actor is outside the DIKW system and outside the realm of computer operations. So, wisdom cannot be placed on the top of the DIKW pyramid as a component of an autonomous logico-deductive structure, rather wisdom bridges the lower levels to human beings and their actions.

Ackoff concludes with some numbers, seemingly produced out of thin air,

on average about forty percent of the human mind consists of data, thirty percent information, twenty percent knowledge, ten percent understanding, and virtually no wisdom (Ackoff 1989, 3)

The DIKW suggests that there are more data than information in the world, more information than knowledge and more knowledge than wisdom [3].

[top of entry]

3. Background concepts

The core concepts in the DIKW-model are data, information, knowledge, and wisdom. This section will present some of the commonly used explications of these notions. In Section 3.1 the concepts of → documents (records, recordings, inscriptions, representational artefacts, informative objects etc.) is introduced and in the conclusion (Section 7) we will briefly consider the absence of another concept: sign.

[top of entry]

3.1 Data

[Also see the article on → Data].

We will assume that data have, or can have, linguistic representation as true or false statements. (The reasons for making this assumption will become clear as the discussion develops. To anticipate: it is required for logic and reasoning, for epistemology, and for Bayesianism.)

Accounts of the concept of data have a long and varied history (Furner 2016; Rowley 2007; Zins 2007). And those accounts often intertwine with accounts of evidence and accounts of facts. Data is “given”, or a datum is “a given”. As Machlup writes:

Data are the things given to the analyst, investigator, or problem-solver; they may be numbers, words, sentences, records, assumptions — just anything given, no matter what form and of what origin. This used to be well known to scholars in most fields: some wanted the word data to refer to facts, especially to instrument-readings; others to assumptions. Scholars with a hypothetico-deductive bent wanted data to mean the given set of assumptions; those with an empirical bent wanted data to mean the records, or protocol statements, representing the findings of observation, qualitative or quantitative (Machlup 1983, 646).

Seemingly, being a “given” really amounts to possessing two features: truth and certainty. Maybe data should be true, and maybe data should be known for certain to be true.

What about the first feature, its truth? We definitely talk of mistaken data, incorrect data, invalid data, wrong data, etc. all the time. But is mistaken data still data? Strictly speaking it is not (just as counterfeit money is not money). When we discover that a specific “datum” is mistaken, we can and should correct our records of it. The reason we do this is the supposition of success (that is why we make all the fuss about how we collect data, and make all the fuss about reliability and validity). Data is used for various purposes, to test theories and be evidence for them, to determine parameters, to answer questions, to be input for calculations, etc. These roles pre-suppose the truth of data. Data needs to be true.

The second presumed feature of data, its certainty, fails, or requires modification. Data is not known for certain to be true. Data is fallible and conjectural. This conclusion follows from the philosophical result that there is no certain knowledge. All knowledge is conjectural (Musgrave 1993). That we are fallibilists means that we never know (know for certain) that data is true, but, nonetheless, data needs to be true (see also Haack 1999; Musgrave 1993).

Data is akin to evidence. Data often is evidence. There are theories and theories of evidence. A central, widespread, and maybe the best, current theory of evidence is Bayesianism (Howson and Urbach 2006; Jaynes 2003). Under Bayesianism, evidence has to be true. Bayesians are fallibilists. They know that there is a difficulty in knowing (for certain) what is true. So they make the requirement that evidence is assumed to be a given (relative to the context of discussion and particular Bayesian inferences).

Data is also akin to facts or (true) factual statements. Once again there are theories and theories of facts, but it is pretty mainstream to adopt a refined common sense and take it that facts are what true statements assert. Under the theory of data offered here, data is indeed similar to facts.

There are some points to be made about the logical form and logical strength of data statements. The temperature at a particular time on a particular day is a singular piece of data; it is a particular fact; it is a logical atom. There might be several such atoms, and these can be combined in various ways using the standard operations of, perhaps, first order logic (FOL) (Sowa 2000) i.e. using “and”, “or”, “not” etc. to make more statements. But there are also universal statements, such as “Every day the maximum temperature is above 50 degrees”. Many, indeed very many, universal statements will be true (and so are candidates for being data under the characterization of data given thus far). But these universal statements are stronger, from a logical point of view, than atoms or compounds of atoms, and thus it is more difficult to be assured about their truth. Crudely, our knowledge of the universal is more fallible than our knowledge of the singular. A fallibilist would prefer to be accepting as data the truth of a judgment of the form “There is a white X” to one of the form “All Xs are white”. It is possible to give a logical characterization of this feature of how strong or how weak data statements should be. Karl Popper did it with his notion of “basic statement” (Popper 1959). Basic statements, logical atoms and compounds of atoms, can be expressed by existential-conjunctive (EC) logic. EC logic is FOL with its logical operators restricted to existential quantifiers and conjunction only (i.e. it does not have negation, implication, disjunction, functions, or the universal quantifier). EC logic is a fragment of FOL, a fragment which focuses on positive assertions. EC logic captures concrete facts. This fits neatly with Ackoff’s views. Ackoff wrote:

Data are symbols that represent properties of objects, events and their environments. (Ackoff 1989, 3)

EC logic does this. There is also a technical result of import here. EC Logic captures exactly those statements held in ordinary computer databases.

Every database used by [SQL, Prolog, Microplanner] – as well as every commercial database, whether relational, hierarchical, or object-oriented implements the existential-conjunctive subset of logic. (Sowa 2000, 163)

And statements of EC logic can be put into a relational database, say, merely by adding the appropriate n-tuple for each atom (i.e. for each concrete fact) (Codd 1970). EC logic is also widely used in artificial intelligence, in theorem proving, and in machine learning. Thus, EC logic sits comfortably with the modern idea of reasoning from big data.

Moving on. Data might be of a number of different kinds. There can be empirical data, for example about daily temperatures at a particular place and time. There can be non-empirical data, for example, the mathematical data that there are four prime numbers between 10 and 20. There can be non-empirical data in the context of fiction, for example, it is a datum that Sherlock Holmes lived at 221B Baker Street. And there are many more types of data besides (see, for example, Kaase 2001). As a source from the literature, Nielsen and Hjørland (2014) argue that data is contextual and related to human activities, then there are many kinds of human activities, ergo there are many kinds of data. To keep the present discussion manageable, it will focus on plain empirical data about the world.

The essence of knowledge organization, or knowledge management, is that they deal with documents (or records, recordings, inscriptions, informative objects and representational artefacts, etc.). Documents are culturally developed ways of communicating knowledge, information and data, and their different kinds or genres are specialized tools for such communication. → Library and information science and → knowledge organization are mainly about classifying, indexing and retrieving documents, and such activities cannot be adequately understood and researched without the concept document.

This invites the suggestion that the notion of data, of interest to knowledge organization, in the context of DIKW, is that of anything recordable in a database in a semantically and pragmatically sound way. The semantics require that the recordings be understood as true or false statements. The pragmatics require that we favor recording what seem to be concrete facts i.e. singular and relatively weak statements, and that interpreted recordings be true statements (and we have to use conjectures on this). Still, it is important to consider that data are constructed from a certain perspective and for a certain purpose that put limits to its use in other contexts.

[top of entry]

3.2 Information

[Also see the article on → Information].

What about information? Information can be, and has been, construed to be

  • knowledge, personal or public,
  • the physical manifestation of knowledge,
  • a state or structure transformer,
  • knowledge or belief new to subject,
  • a member of the data-information-knowledge-(wisdom/understanding) hierarchy,
  • a construct in thermodynamics,
  • entropy or negentropy,
  • reduction in uncertainty,
  • signal information,
  • content or semantic information,
  • truthlike information,
  • patterns,

and, many more things besides (Bates 2005; 2006; Belkin 1978; Boell and Cecez-Kecmanovic 2011; 2015; Capurro and Hjørland 2003; Frické 1997; Furner 2014; Ma 2012; Robinson and Bawden 2014).

As Floridi writes

Information is notoriously a polymorphic phenomenon and a polysemantic concept so, as an explicandum, it can be associated with several explanations, depending on the level of abstraction adopted and the cluster of requirements and desiderata orientating a theory (Floridi 2004, 117).

Working broad brush, these accounts of information can be characterized as being syntactic or semantic. Syntactic information, such as Shannon’s signal information, Chaitin’s Kolmogorov complexity, thermodynamic entropy, Fisher information etc. (Chaitin 1987; Pierce 1980; Shannon and Weaver 1949), have been considered important for information science but have a controversial status (cf. Hjørland 2018, 239-42) [4]. In the context of the DIKW pyramid, with the desire to talk about data, knowledge, and wisdom, syntactic information is not the concept in use. The DIKW pyramid is not about juggling and permuting inscriptions in an accurate and efficient way. Instead the concept employed is semantic information. This is the concept where attention is paid to the meaning and truth, and other semantic properties, of the recorded marks.

Within accounts of semantic information there are many theories and a number of live issues. Need information be true? Is misinformation and disinformation real information? Need information be new to the user? Must someone be “informed” by it, for it to be information? There are open questions about which reasonable researchers can disagree. Even so, a proposal can be placed on the table. The focus of interest in this context is both information science and data. Librarians, information scientists and people associated with knowledge organization often use knowledge and information as synonyms, and they need not be widely wrong to do so [5]. Information can be taken to be the recorded counterpart of true propositions i.e. so-called “weak knowledge” or “weak public knowledge”.

The concepts of knowledge, weak knowledge, and weak public knowledge will be explained in the next section. Suffice it to say, for the present, weak public knowledge are community held views which are true.

The interim conclusions are these. There are many different senses of information. There are even many different senses of information in use in information science. It is not the case that one of these senses is good, and all purpose, and the others deficient. But, both in information science and elsewhere, there are different problems and different contexts where these different notions of information come into play. As Shannon wrote:

The word “information” has been given different meanings by various writers in the general field of information theory. It is likely that at least a number of these will prove sufficiently useful in certain applications to deserve further study and permanent recognition. It is hardly to be expected that a single concept of information would satisfactorily account for the numerous possible applications of this general field. (Shannon 1993, 180, emphasis original)

And, when the focus is on DIKW, so-called “weak knowledge” may prove suitable as an account of information.

[top of entry]

3.3 Knowledge

A distinction with knowledge is that between knowledge-that and knowledge-how. Knowledge, in the sense of a knowledge base or knowledge within traditional philosophy, is just a collection of propositional “know-thats” for example, a person might know that the Eiffel Tower is in Paris and know that the Channel Tunnel connects England and France. Additionally, using a different concept, that very same person might know how to ride a bicycle. This latter is a different kind of knowledge, it is skill or “know-how” (Carr 1979; Ryle 1946; Snowdon 2003).

In philosophy, personal know-thats have been given a basic explication in terms of justified, true, belief (Plato 370 BCE). A person knows that p if, and only if,

p is true,
the person believes p, and
the person is justified in her belief of p.

This analysis is a proposal in answer to the question “What do I know?”, which is a personal question. But there is another know-that epistemological question, namely, “What is known?” and this is seeking an analysis of public knowledge. Typically, the analysis of public knowledge, impersonal knowledge, would be

p is true,
p is accepted by the community,
the community has evidence or justification for p.

While the standard justified-true-belief account of personal knowledge, and justified-true-(community-accepted) account of public knowledge, are absolutely central and widespread within traditional philosophy (Musgrave 1993), they are by no means universal with modern philosophers. Many contemporary epistemologists make a distinction between strong and weak knowledge, Goldman (1999) is one example. Strong knowledge covers justified-true-beliefs and justified-true-(community-accepted)-statements. Weak knowledge is like strong knowledge except that the justification component is omitted. Thus, weak personal knowledge consists of beliefs which are true, and weak impersonal knowledge consists of community held views which are true. It has been suggested earlier that the concept of weak personal or public knowledge, in its recorded form, is suitable as a view of information.

Ackoff, and the early systems theorists, tend to use a “know-how” concept of knowledge. Examples of know how are that a person knows how to ride a bike, or knows how to play chess. There are philosophical accounts of know-how (see, for example, Fantl 2016). Know-how is often analyzed in terms of ability: a person knows how to ride a bike if they have the ability to ride a bike. Another strand that can feed into the analysis is intellectualist vs. anti-intellectualist approaches and this is to do with the extent to which know-how is parasitic, symbiotic, or dependent, upon know-that. An intellectualist might say that, in chess, if a person knows that a pawn can advance two squares on the first move, knows that bishops move diagonally, etc. etc. then that person knows how to play chess. In other words, knowing how to play chess merely amounts to knowing a suitable collection of know-thats. This intellectualist account is much less plausible with a case like riding a bike. Which know-thats, exactly, does a bike rider have to have in order to know how to ride a bike? The bike rider cannot say, nor, seemingly, can anyone else. At this point the anti-intellectualist might trumpet: know-hows have nothing to do with know-thats. This might be a reasonable conclusion, but the intellectualist is not quite dead yet. The intellectualist can introduce the idea of tacit knowledge (Polanyi 1958; 1967). This is knowledge, know-that knowledge, that someone has but which they cannot say, articulate, or put into words. In general, there is plenty of tacit knowledge (though there is a question of whether that concept belongs here). So, the intellectualist might argue that the know-how of a bike rider is dependent on a collection of know-thats, but the know-thats are tacit and difficult to make explicit.

The Ackoff tradition uses know-how and it relates that to ability. DIKW swirls in data and information, which is to suggest that DIKW has a lot of connection at the lower levels with propositions and know-thats. This, in turn, suggests that the systems theories would take an intellectualist view of know-how (that know-how is intimately related to know-that). Finally, this position really requires some use of tacit knowledge.

[top of entry]

3.4 Wisdom

That leaves wisdom. The concept of wisdom certainly occupied the ancient Greek philosophers, such as Plato and Aristotle; although it has not been a popular topic of discussion in recent times. There seem to be several different strands to wisdom (Ryan 2013; Sternberg 1990; 2017). A wise person needs to have an understanding of the epistemic status of what he or she knows i.e. they have to be a fallibilist — Socrates was considered wise largely because all he knew was that he knew nothing. Then, almost in contradiction to this, a wise person has to know, fallibly, plenty. A person that genuinely knows little or nothing, a person with an empty head, is not a wise person. Then this wide knowledge has to be of a certain kind, a kind that applies to the many and varied problems of life. A person may have encyclopedic knowledge of the facts and figures relating to the countries of the world; but that knowledge, of itself, will not make that person wise. The wide knowledge has to be applicable to tricky problems of an ethical and practical kind, of how to act.

Wisdom is not just one type of knowledge, but diverse. What a wise person needs to know and understand constitutes a varied list: the most important goals and values of life — the ultimate goal, if there is one; what means will reach these goals without too great a cost; what kinds of dangers threaten the achieving of these goals; how to recognize and avoid or minimize these dangers; what different types of human beings are like in their actions and motives (as this presents dangers or opportunities); what is not possible or feasible to achieve (or avoid); how to tell what is appropriate when; knowing when certain goals are sufficiently achieved; what limitations are unavoidable and how to accept them; how to improve oneself and one's relationships with others or society; knowing what the true and unapparent value of various things is; when to take a long-term view; knowing the variety and obduracy of facts, institutions, and human nature; understanding what one's real motives are; how to cope and deal with the major tragedies and dilemmas of life, and with the major good things too. (Nozick 1989, 269)

And the wise person must not only have wide appropriate knowledge, but they must act in accordance with the knowledge they have — they need to use their knowledge when required, and not to ignore it by choice or chance.

The DIKW account of wisdom, in its Ackoff version, is reasonably in harmony with this. Ackoff, and his immediate followers, were systems theorists, they were control theorists. Knowledge, was know-how, know how to control the systems. Then wisdom was merely a matter of using that practical know how to achieve appropriate ends.

[top of entry]

4. Modern developments, variations, and rebuttals of DIKW

There are publications that argue that DIKW should be “top-down”. Tuomi (1999) favors inverting DIKW so that it becomes top-down. The argument here is hypothetico-deductivism combined with the theory-ladeness observations (emphasized elsewhere by Hanson 1958 and Kuhn 1962). The suggestion is that there is no such thing as “raw data”, rather all data must have theory in it and thus theory (i.e. knowledge, information) must illuminate data, top down, rather than the other way around, bottom up. Sato and Huang (2015) also emphasize the need for knowledge and information to highlight data, as does Weinberger (2010). Frické (2009) also presents top-down reasoning, but he goes further. He argues that DIKW should be abandoned completely. His position develops from a Popperian fallibilist realism, combined with hypothetico-deductivism and a modesty about humankind’s place in reality. He identifies in DIKW an operationalist thread and an inductivist thread — both of which are anathemas to his starting position. Frické reasons that some information is universal in form and as such could not have been derived from data.

There are publications that add or subtract layers from DIKW. Hoppe et al. (2011) suggest omitting wisdom from the DIKW pyramid (to leave a DIK pyramid). Their paper provides an insightful discussion of wisdom and DIKW. They summarize common points in definitions of wisdom:

  • based on a special kind of knowledge: It is agreed that a certain type of knowledge is needed to develop wisdom, whereas the definite type is hardly described?
  • controlled emotion: Wisdom is neither pure rationality, nor pure emotion based; it creates a certain kind of “intuition”?
  • creativity: wise solutions often include a novel approach to a problem, a creative interconnection of knowledge and experience that leads to a better performance?
  • wise behaviour: the attribute “wise” is mostly awarded to a certain behaviour, seldomly to a person, never to a mere fact?
  • connected to special circumstances: a behaviour is not generally wise, but depends on the situation it happens in, the judging observer, the epoch,...?
  • peak-performance: Wisdom is a peak performance one can only achieve with a large amount of experience, knowledge and probably with age (Hoppe et al. 2011, 588)
  • They argue that the concept of wisdom is both an imprecise concept and fuzzy concept. They note, in a way following Ackoff, that wisdom is different kind or category of thing to data, information, and knowledge. They suggest that it should be removed from the DIKW hierarchy. In contrast, Pop, Talpos and Prisac (2015) would like DIKW expanded to DIMLAK (Data, Information, Messages, Learning, and Advanced Knowledge).

    There are publications that draw DIKW more into management practices. Jennex (2009) suggests that

    the knowledge pyramid is an artifact of KM [Knowledge Management] processes and not an artifact of reality…. the knowledge pyramid is an artificially constructed artifact representing the relationship between DIKW in an organizational KM context. (Jennex 2009, 1)

    Jennex argues that DIKW does not stand on its own, rather it exists in the context of organizational learning. He also makes the point that managers or organizations are not interested in knowledge or wisdom in general, rather they are interested in knowledge or wisdom in settings relevant to what they do:

    knowledge management is not trying to capture all knowledge or wisdom. Rather, knowledge management targets specific knowledge and wisdom needed by an organization to perform specific tasks. (Jennex 2009, 4)

    Müller and Maasdorp (2011) analyze the presumed role of DIKW within Knowledge Management as a theory of a flow of decisions within an organizational context.

    However, we approach information science as a management and organizationally driven field rather than a computationally and information systems oriented one. This means that information theory and the associated versions of communication theory do not explain or shed much light on dynamics that are significant in management and organization. A focus on social science and philosophical ideas of the socially and linguistically embedded nature of knowledge enables us to reflect on organizational processes in a particular way, but it also allows us to critique the dominant view of information systems, arguing instead that information systems can and should also be conceptualized as flow of decisions that are set in an organizational context. (Müller and Maasdorp 2011, 1)

    There are publications in a more general category. Baskarada and Koronios (2013) introduce quality into the discussion, not as a separate entity unto itself, but rather in the context of the quality of data, quality of information, quality of knowledge, and quality of wisdom. They set the DIKW pyramid within a semiotic analysis. Finally, they do a content analysis of the occurrence of the DIKW terms, and DIKW and quality terms, within online news articles. One conclusion they reach is:

    The paper [… provides] further evidence for the lack of consistency in how the relevant terms are used in every-day language as well as by information systems experts. (Baskarada and Koronios 2013, 18)

    Finally, there are publications which take DIKW into other cultures. Mercier, Stevens and Toia (2012) interface DIKW with the New Zealand Māori culture.

    [top of entry]

    5. Drawing it all together


    5.1 The logico-conceptual point of view

    From a logico-conceptual point of view, DIKW seems not to work.

    5.1.1 Data to information

    Ackoff (1989) urges us to gather data with measuring instruments and sensors. But instruments are constructed in the light of theories, and theories are essential to inform us of what the surface indications of the instruments are telling us about a reality beyond the instruments themselves (Bogen 2013). A datum is a proposition like “the voltage in the circuit is 2 volts”; it is not an item like “the needle on the voltmeter points to 2”; and getting from one to the other requires theories. Data is “theory-laden” (Tuomi 1999).

    Data itself can be more than the mere “observable”, and it can be more than the pronouncements of “instruments”. There are contexts, conventions, and pragmatics at work. In particular circumstances, researchers might regard some recordings as data which report matters that are neither observable nor determinable by instrument (Nielsen and Hjørland 2014).

    All data is information. However, there is information that is not data. Information can range much more widely than data; it can be much more extensive than the given. For example, consider the universal statement “All rattlesnakes are dangerous”. This statement presumably is, or might be, information, yet it cannot be inferred from data. The problem is with the universality, with the “All”. Any data, or conjunctions of data, are singular. For example, “Rattlesnake A is dangerous”, “Rattlesnake B is dangerous”, “Rattlesnake C is dangerous”, etc. are singular in form. Trying to make the inference from “some” to “all’ is an inductive inference, and inductive inferences are invalid. The point can be made solely in terms of logic. Data typically is expressed by existential-conjunctive logic, information requires the full first order logic; the latter cannot even be expressed in its entirety by the former; and, in particular, some statements in the latter amount to information and they cannot be inferred from the former (Frické 2009).

    Another argument that can be used against a proposed data to information step uses the observable-theoretical distinction. Within scientific and other theories there are often terms that are “observable” and other terms which are “theoretical” (Carnap 1956). Observable terms refer to observable properties such as blue, warm, and contiguous with. Theoretical terms refer theoretical entities (i.e. non-observable entities) for example, electrons, neutrons, and genes. In Ackoff’s view, data in the DIKW pyramid concerns observable properties, but in the world of science there is some information which concerns theoretical terms or theoretical properties. For example, the mass of an electron is 9.10938356 × 10-31 kilograms. This statement of mass is information, but it is not data, or a datum, because it does not relate to observable properties. Therefore, there is at least some information which has not come from data as observational units.

    [top of entry]

    5.1.2 Information to knowledge

    The step from information to knowledge is also not the easiest. If knowledge is construed as “know-that”, then, under some views of information and knowledge, information and knowledge are much the same. In which case moving from information to knowledge might not be so hard. However, in the context of DIKW, knowledge is usually taken to be “know-how”, and that makes the step difficult. Consider a young person learning how to ride a bike. What information in particular is required? It is hard to say, and maybe no information in particular is required. However, like many skills, riding a bike is definitely coachable, and information can improve performance. For example, the information that a bike rider’s having the weight on the outside pedal and the inside handle bar end is pretty well optimal for cornering, or the information that a bike rider lowering body position and reducing frontal area reduces aerodynamic drag, can improve bike riding skill. Know-how can benefit from information. The problem is in the details. All know-thats are propositional in form and, given a suitable expressing language, they can be written down and recorded or stored in data-bases. Know-hows are different. Some know-hows might be articulated as procedural rules, usually “if-then” rules. Knowing how to solve a quadratic equation, how to bid at Contract Bridge, and similar, might be conceived like this. Such rules, of course, can be written down and stored in a repository. Other know-hows do not seem to be of this kind. Knowing how to ride a bicycle is not plausibly a matter of the brain scanning, and selecting among, rules like “if you want to turn left, lean left”. So, much of know-how cannot really be explicitly recorded. Within cognitive science, there is the different distinction between “procedural” and “declarative” knowledge (Anderson 1976; Newell 1972). Declarative knowledge amounts to the know-thats of philosophy. But procedural knowledge is inexpressible. So, someone might learn to ride of bicycle from a book by following declarative knowledge rules like “if you want to turn left, lean left” then, when the rider masters the skill, that declarative knowledge dissolves into the inherently inexpressible procedural knowledge know-how skill of knowing how to ride a bike. As mentioned, another distinction of relevance in this context is Polanyi’s (1958) distinction between tacit and explicit knowledge. Tacit knowledge is the inexpressible personal how-to knowledge of domain experts; explicit knowledge is the expressible and recordable know-that knowledge that, for instance, fills books and libraries. Much of “know-how” and procedural knowledge is tacit. In sum, know-how can involve tacit knowledge, and it may or may not be intellectualist (i.e. re-framable in terms of know-thats). The details of the relationship between information and know-how are unclear.

    [top of entry]

    5.1.3. Knowledge to wisdom

    Wisdom is in an entirely different category to data, information, and know-how. Wisdom certainly uses or needs data, information and know-how, but it uses and needs more besides. Wisdom is not a distillation of data, information, and know-how. Wisdom does not belong at the top of a DIKW pyramid. Basically, this is acknowledged implicitly by all writers on the topic, from Plato, through Ackoff, to modern researchers.

    [top of entry]

    5.2 DIKW in the setting of work processes

    So much for DIKW considered logico-conceptually, what about DIKW in the setting of work processes? Frické (2009) argues that the DIKW theory seems to encourage uninspired methodology. The DIKW view is that data, existing data that has been collected, is promoted to information and that information answers questions. This encourages the mindless and meaningless collection of data in the hope that one day it will ascend to information — i.e. pre-emptive acquisition. It also leads to the desire for “data warehouses”, with contents that are to be analyzed by “data mining”. Collecting data also is very much in harmony with the modern “big data” approach to solving problems. Big data, and data mining are somewhat controversial (Austin and Goldwasser 2008; Austin et al. 2006; Dye 2007; Frické 2015). The worry is that collecting data blind is suspect methodologically. An analogue of an information scientist collecting data is a scientist collecting observations. Popper (1963) writes about that:

    the belief that we can start with pure observations alone, without anything in the nature of a theory, is absurd; as may be illustrated by the story of the man who dedicated his life to natural science, wrote down everything he could observe, and bequeathed his priceless collection of observations to the Royal Society to be used as inductive evidence. This story should show us that though beetles may profitably be collected, observations may not. (Popper 1963, 46)

    Also, analyzing “raw” data — data without background theory — can lead to all sorts of unsound statistical manipulations (Bretz and Hsu 2007; Cohen 1994; Frické 2015; Huff 1954; Johansson 2011; Meehl 1978; Mills 1993). A manager of information does not want to be collecting data hoping that it might be promoted to information. A better methodology is more top-down and just-in-time. A good theory of questions may delimit exactly the information needed to answer a particular question; and then the raising of a question will itself direct the search for information, observations, or data.

    As mentioned, know-how can be improved by information. But the situation here is again that of requiring top-down background knowledge or theorizing. A manager will often have a template of the know-how; the manager will know most everything except for some parameters or particular details. Information might give those details. To revisit an earlier quotation, Ackoff asserts:

    Knowledge is know-how, for example, how a system works. It is what makes possible the transformation of information into instructions. It makes control of a system possible. (Ackoff 1989, 4)

    If know-how is going to become instructions, it should not be the ineffable procedural knowledge of cognitive science, nor should it be philosophy’s inarticulable know-how of mundane skills (like bike riding). It should not be tacit. What Ackoff attempts is not the best way to approach what he is aiming for. What is best, is to take knowledge to be know-that. Then some of those explicit know-thats will be rules or instructions (like “if the thermostat is set lower, the room will become cooler”). All of these can be recorded and stored and thus have a role central to the province of “information management, information systems and knowledge management literatures”.

    Know-how in management is simply more involved than DIKW depicts it. As Weinberger (2010) writes:

    knowledge is not a result merely of filtering or algorithms. It results from a far more complex process that is social, goal-driven, contextual, and culturally-bound. We get to knowledge — especially “actionable” knowledge — by having desires and curiosity, through plotting and play, by being wrong more often than right, by talking with others and forming social bonds, by applying methods and then backing away from them, by calculation and serendipity, by rationality and intuition, by institutional processes and social roles. Most important in this regard, where the decisions are tough and knowledge is hard to come by, knowledge is not determined by information, for it is the knowing process that first decides which information is relevant, and how it is to be used.

    Wisdom is important in management and decision making, and there is a literature on this (see, for example, Sternberg 2017). But, seemingly, no one wants to relate wisdom in management to the DIKW pyramid.

    In sum, DIKW does not sit well in modern business process theory. To quote Weinberger (2010) again:

    The real problem with the DIKW pyramid is that it’s a pyramid. The image that knowledge (much less wisdom) results from applying finer-grained filters at each level, paints the wrong picture. That view is natural to the Information Age which has been all about filtering noise, reducing the flow to what is clean, clear and manageable. Knowledge is more creative, messier, harder won, and far more discontinuous.

    [top of entry]

    6. Conclusion

    What are the general implications of this analysis of the DIKW-pyramid for knowledge organization?

    If the DIKW model was adequate, knowledge organization could be understood as a purely inductive process based on data as units. Because of issues such as the theory-laden nature of perception, there is, however, a two-way interactive process between data and knowledge: Knowledge influences what is considered data and data take part in building knowledge. Knowledge organization is therefore not just based on empiricism and induction, which may be considered unfruitful philosophical positions. Data may be understood as what is or can be represented in databases [6]. Contrary to the empiricist/inductivist philosophy behind the DIKW-model the pragmatic semiotics of Charles Sanders Peirce, and the concept of sign [7] is based on an advanced understanding on how objects in the world, their symbols and their interpretations are interrelated. From this perspective, the DIKW-model seems naïve and problematic. This demonstrates – again – that theoretical issues in knowledge organization are intimately connected with epistemological theories.

    [top of entry]

    Acknowledgement

    This encyclopedia entry uses some passages of background material previously available as part of Frické (2009). The editor of IEKO, Birger Hjørland, has contributed with modifications of the original manuscript, including modifications that are substantial.

    [top of entry]

    Endnotes

    1. Hopefully, this encyclopedia (IEKO) will also at a later point have independent articles of each of these concepts.

    2. "Where is the life | we have lost in living? | Where is the wisdom | we have lost in knowledge? | Where is the knowledge | we have lost in information?" (Eliot 1934, 7, "Choruses", Chorus 1)

    3. Jennex and Bartczak (2013) suggests that the reverse is the case: there is more information than data, more knowledge than information and more wisdom than knowledge.

    4. In particular, the physical transmission of encoded information, its compression and error correction via Huffman trees, Hamming codes and the like, have their theoretical foundation with Shannon (Pierce 1980).

    5. For example, Svenonius (2000) uses “information organization” for what is commonly termed “knowledge organization”.

    6. Databases as well as their individual records may be understood as kinds of documents. In the case of bibliographical databases, they represent metadata or metadocuments about other documents.

    7. ”A sign, or representamen, is something which stands to somebody for something in some respect or capacity. It addresses somebody, that is, creates in the mind of that person an equivalent sign, or perhaps a more developed sign. That sign which it creates I call the interpretant of the first sign. The sign stands for something, its object. It stands for that object not in all respects, but in reference to a sort of idea, which I have sometimes called the ground of the representamen” (Peirce 1960, CP 2.228).

    [top of entry]

    References

    Ackoff, Russell L. 1989. "From Data to Wisdom." Journal of Applied Systems Analysis 16: 3–9.

    Adler, Mortimer J. 1986. A Guidebook to Learning: For a Lifelong Pursuit of Wisdom. New York: Macmillan.

    Anderson, John Robert. 1976. Language, Memory, and Thought. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Austin, Peter C., and Meredith A. Goldwasser. 2008. "Pisces did not have Increased Heart Failure: Data-driven Comparisons of Binary Proportions between Levels of a Categorical Variable can Result in Incorrect Statistical Significance Levels." Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 61, no. 3: 295-300.

    Austin, Peter C., Muhammad M. Mamdani, David N. Juurlink, and Janet E. Hux. 2006. "Testing Multiple Statistical Hypotheses Resulted in Spurious Associations: a Study of Astrological Signs and Health." Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 59, no. 9: 871-2.

    Baskarada, Sasa and Andy Koronios. 2013. "Data, Information, Knowledge, Wisdom (DIKW): A Semiotic Theoretical and Empirical Exploration of the Hierarchy and its Quality Dimension." Australasian Journal of Information Systems 18, no. 1, 5-24. doi: 10.3127/ajis.v18i1.748.

    Bates, Marcia J. 2005. "Information and Knowledge: an Evolutionary Framework for Information Science." Information Research 10 (4): paper 239. http://www.informationr.net/ir/10-4/paper239.html

    Bates, Marcia J. 2006. "Fundamental Forms of Information." Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 57, no. 8: 1033-45.

    Bawden, David, and Lyn Robinson. 2015. "Information and the Gaining of Understanding." Journal of Information Science 42, no. 3: 294–9.

    Bedford, Denise A. D, and John Lewis. 2015. "Introduction to the Special Issue: Knowledge Management Models and Theories." Journal of Information & Knowledge Management 14, no. 4: 1-4.

    Belkin, Nicholas J. 1978. "Information Concepts for Information Science". Journal of Documentation 34, no. 1: 55-85.

    Boell, Sebastian and Dubravka Cecez-Kecmanovic. 2011. "Theorizing Information – From Signs to Sociomaterial Practices." ACIS 2011 Proceedings. Paper 53. https://aisel.aisnet.org/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1052&context=acis2011

    Boell, Sebastian, and Dubravka Cecez-Kecmanovic. 2015. "What is ‘Information’ Beyond a Definition?" Proceedings of the Thirty Sixth International Conference on Information Systems, ICIS 2015: Exploring the Information Frontier, edited by Traci Carte, Armin Heinzl and Cathy Urquhart. Atlanta, GA: Association for Information Systems, 1-20.

    Bogen, Jim. 2013. "Theory and Observation in Science". In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition), edited by Edward N. Zalta.

    Bretz, Frank, and Jason C. Hsu (eds.) 2007. “Special issue on Multiplicity in Pharmaceutical Statistics”. Pharmaceutical Statistics 6, no. 3: 151-250.

    Capurro, Rafael and Birger Hjørland. 2003. "The Concept of Information". Annual Review of Information Science and Technology 37: 343–411.

    Carnap, Rudolf. 1956. "The Methodological Character of Theoretical Concepts". In Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, edited by Herbert Feigl and Michael Scriven. Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press, 38-76. https://conservancy.umn.edu/bitstream/handle/11299/184284/1_02_Carnap.pdf?sequence=3

    Carr, David. 1979. "The Logic of Knowing How and Ability". Mind 88: 394-409.

    Chaitin, Gregory J. 1987. Information, Randomness & Incompleteness: Papers on Algorithmic Information Theory. Vol. 8, World Scientific Series in Computer Science. Singapore: Teaneck, NJ, USA.

    Cleveland, Harlan. 1982. "Information as a Resource". The Futurist 16, no. 6: 34–9.

    Codd, Edgar F. 1970. "A Relational Model of Data for Large Shared Data Banks". Communications of the ACM 13, no. 6: 377-87.

    Cohen, Jacob. 1994. "The Earth is Round (p<.05)". American Psychologist 49 (12):997-1003.

    Dalal, Nikunj. 2012. "Wisdom Computing: Toward a Framework for Wisdom Research in Information Systems". AMCIS 2012 Proceedings. 14. http://aisel.aisnet.org/amcis2012/proceedings/PerspectivesIS/14

    Dinneen, Jesse David, and Christian Brauner. 2015. "Practical and Philosophical Considerations for Defining Information as Well-formed, Meaningful Data in the Information Sciences". Library Trends 63, no. 3: 378-400.

    Duffield, Stephen, and S Jonathan Whitty. 2015. "Developing a Systemic Lessons Learned Knowledge Model for Organisational Learning through Projects". International journal of project management 33, no. 2: 311-24.

    Dye, Lee. 2007. "Do Libras Live Longer?", accessed March 20 2008. http://abcnews.go.com/Technology/Story?id=2890150&page=1.

    Eliot, Thomas Stearns. 1934. The rock. London: Faber & Faber.

    Fantl, Jeremy. 2016. "Knowledge How". In The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2016 Edition),, edited by Edward N. Zalta.

    Floridi, Luciano. 2004. "Information". In The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Computing and Information, edited by L. Floridi. Oxford - New York: Blackwell, 40-61.

    Floridi, Luciano. 2011. The Philosophy of Information. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Frické, Martin. 1997. "Information using Likeness Measures". Journal of the American Society for Information Science 48, no. 10: 882-92.

    Frické, Martin. 2009. "The Knowledge Pyramid: a Critique of the DIKW Hierarchy". Journal of Information Science 35, no. 2: 131-42. doi: 10.1177/0165551508094050.

    Frické, Martin. 2015. "Big Data and its Epistemology". Journal of the Association for Information Science and Technology 66, no. 4: 651-61.

    Furner, Jonathan. 2014. "Information Without Information Studies". In Theories of Information, Communication and Knowledge: A Multidisciplinary Approach, edited by Fidelia Ibekwe-SanJuan and Thomas M. Dousa. Dordrecht: Springer, 143-79.

    Furner, Jonathan. 2016. "’Data’: The Data". In Information Cultures in the Digital Age: A Festschrift in Honor of Rafael Capurro, edited by Matthew KellyJared and Bielby. Wiesbaden: Springer, 287-306.

    Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a Social World. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Haack, Susan. 1999. "A Fallibilist among the Cynics". Skeptical Inquirer 23, no. 1: 47-50.

    Hanson, Norwood Russell. 1958. Patterns of Discovery. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Hjørland, Birger. 2018. “Library and Information Science (LIS) Part 1”. Knowledge Organization 45, no. 3: 232-54. Also available at: https://www.isko.org/cyclo/lis

    Hoppe, Anett, Rudolf Seising, Andreas Nürnberger, and Constanze Wenzel. 2011. "Wisdom - the Blurry Top of Human Cognition in the DIKW-model?". Paper presented at the meeting of the EUSFLAT Conference 2011. EUSFLAT, Jul 2011, Aix-Les-Bains, France. 1 (1), 584 – 91. DOI: 10.2991/eusflat.2011.91

    Howson, Colin, and Peter Urbach. 2006. Scientific Reasoning: the Bayesian Approach. 3rd ed. Chicago: Open Court.

    Huff, Darrell. 1954. How to Lie with Statistics. New York: W.W. Norton.

    Jaynes, Edwin Thompson. 2003. Probability Theory: the Logic of Science. Edited by G. Larry Bretthorst. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Jennex, Murray E. 2009. "Re-Visiting the Knowledge Pyramid." Proceedings of the 42nd Hawaii International Conference on Systems Sciences, HICSS. 1-7. DOI: 10.1109/HICSS.2009.361

    Jennex, Murray E., and Summer E. Bartczak. 2013. "A Revised Knowledge Pyramid". International Journal of Knowledge Management 9, no. 3: 19-30. doi: 10.4018/ijkm.2013070102.

    Johansson, Tobias. 2011. "Hail the Impossible: P-values, Evidence, and Likelihood". Scandanavian Journal of Psychology 52, no. 2: 113-25.

    Kaase, Max. 2001. "Databases, Core: Political Science and Political Behavior". In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, edited by Neil Smelser and Paul B. Baltes. Amsterdam: Elsevier, 3251-5.

    KM4DEV. 2012. "DIKW model". http://wiki.km4dev.org/DIKW_model.

    Kuhn, Thomas. S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Lambe, Patrick. 2011. "The Unacknowledged Parentage of Knowledge Management". Journal of Knowledge Management 15, no. 2: 175-97.

    Liew, Anthony. 2013. "DIKIW: Data, Information, Knowledge, Intelligence, Wisdom and their Interrelationships". Business Management Dynamics 2, no. 10: 49-62.

    Ma, Lai. 2012. "Meanings of Information: The Assumptions and Research Consequences of Three Foundational LIS Theories". Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 63, no. 4: 716-23.

    Machlup, Fritz. 1983. "Semantic Quirks in Studies of Information". In The Study of Information: Interdisciplinary Messages, edited by Fritz Machlup and Una Mansfield. New York, NY: Wiley, 641-71.

    Meehl, Paul E. 1978. "Theoretical Risks and Tabular Asterisks: Sir Karl, Sir Ronald, and the Slow Progress of Soft Psychology". Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology 46: 806-34.

    Mercier, O. Ripeka, Nathan Stevens, and Anaru Toia. 2012. "Mätauranga Mäori and the Data–Information–Knowledge–Wisdom Hierarchy: A Conversation on Interfacing Knowledge Systems". The Mai Journal 1, no. 2: 103-16. http://www.journal.mai.ac.nz/sites/default/files/Pages%20103%20-%20116.pdf

    Mills, James L. 1993. "Data Torturing". New England Journal of Medicine 329, no. 16: 1196-9.

    Müller, Hans, and Christiaan Maasdorp. 2011. "The Data, Information, and Knowledge Hierarchy and its Ability to Convince". Fifth IEEE International Conference on Research Challenges in Information Science, RCIS, Proceedings, Gosier, Guadeloupe, France, May 19- 21 2011. IEEE Xplore. http://ieeexplore.ieee.org/document/6006851/.

    Musgrave, Alan. 1993. Common Sense, Science, and Scepticism: a Historical Introduction to the Theory of Knowledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Book; Internet Resource.

    Newell, Allen and Herbert Alexander Simon. 1972. Human Problem Solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.

    Nielsen, Hans Jørn and Birger Hjørland. 2014. "Curating Research Data: The Potential Roles of Libraries and Information Professionals". Journal of Documentation 70, no. 2: 221-40. doi: 10.1108/jd-03-2013-0034.

    Nozick, Robert. 1989. "What is Wisdom and Why do Philosophers Love It So?" In The Examined Life, edited by Robert Nozick. New York: Touchstone Press, 267-78.

    Peirce, Charles Sanders. 1960. Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Vol. 2 (2.228). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Pierce, John Robinson. 1980. An Introduction to Information Theory: Symbols, Signals & Noise. 2nd, rev. ed. New York: Dover Publications. Book; Internet Resource.

    Plato. 370 BCE. "Theaetetus". accessed 1/1/2017. http://classics.mit.edu/Plato/theatu.html.

    Polanyi, Michael E. 1958. Personal Knowledge: towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Polanyi, Michael E. 1967. The Tacit Dimension. New York: Anchor.

    Pop, Ioan G, Mihai-Florin Talpos, and Igor Prisac. 2016. "A Transdisciplinary Approach on the Advanced Sustainable Knowledge Integration." In The role of engineering/technology and business education in an uncertain future: 7th Balkan Region Conference on Engeneering and Business Education. Lucian Blaga University of Sibiu, 1-4 November 2015, 228-49. DOI: https://doi.org/10.1515/cplbu-2015-0025

    Popper, Karl Raimund. 1959. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. London: Hutchinson.

    Popper, Karl Raimund. 1963. Conjectures and Refutations. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

    Roberts, Joanne. 2015. A Very Short, Fairly Interesting and Reasonably Cheap Book about Knowledge Management. London: Sage.

    Robinson, Lyn, and David Bawden. 2014. "Mind the Gap: Transitions Between Concepts of Information in Varied Domains". In Theories of Information, Communication and Knowledge: A Multidisciplinary Approach, edited by Fidelia Ibekwe-SanJuan and Thomas M. Dousa. Dordrecht: Springer, 121-41.

    Rowley, Jennifer E. 2007. "The Wisdom Hierarchy: Representations of the DIKW hierarchy". Journal of Information Science 33, no. 2: 163-80.

    Ryan, Sharon. 2013. "Wisdom". in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Last Modified 2/4/2013, accessed Jan 15. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/wisdom/.

    Ryle, Gilbert. 1946. "Knowing How and Knowing That". In Collected Papers, Vol II: Collected Essays (1929-1968), edited by Gilbert Ryle. New York: Barnes & Noble, Inc.

    Sato, Atsushi, and Runhe Huang. 2015. "A Generic Formulated KID Model for Pragmatic Processing of Data, Information, and Knowledge." 2015 IEEE 12th Intl Conf on Ubiquitous Intelligence and Computing and 2015 IEEE 12th Intl Conf on Autonomic and Trusted Computing and 2015 IEEE 15th Intl Conf on Scalable Computing and Communications and Its Associated Workshops (UIC-ATC-ScalCom), Beijing, 2015, pp. 609-616. doi: 10.1109/UIC-ATC-ScalCom-CBDCom-IoP.2015.120

    Shannon, Claude Elwood. 1993. Collected Papers. Edited by N.J.A. Sloane and A.D. Wyner. Los Alamos, Ca:: IEEE Computer Society Press.

    Shannon, Claude Elwood, and Warren Weaver. 1949. The Mathematical Theory of Communication. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Sharma, Nikhil. 2008. "The Origin of DIKW Hierarchy". Accessed 12/23/2016. https://erealityhome.wordpress.com/2008/03/09/the-origin-of-dikw-hierarchy/.

    Snowdon, Paul. 2003. "Knowing How and Knowing That: A Distinction Reconsidered". Proceedings of The Aristotelian Society 104, no. 1: 1-29. doi: 10.1111/1467-9264.t01-1-00001.

    Sowa, John F. 2000. Knowledge Representation: Logical, Philosophical, and Computational Foundations. Pacific Grove, CA: Brooks/Cole.

    Sternberg, Robert J. 1990. “Understanding Wisdom”. In Wisdom: its Nature, Origins, and Development, edited by Robet J Sternberg. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 3-12.

    Sternberg, Robert J. 2017. "Balance Theory of Wisdom". accessed 1/15/2017. http://www.robertjsternberg.com/wisdom/.

    Svenonius, Elaine. 2000. The Intellectual Foundation of Information Organization. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Tuomi, Ilkka. 1999. "Data Is More Than Knowledge: Implications of the Reversed Knowledge Hierarchy for Knowledge Management and Organizational Memory". Proceedings of the 32nd Hawaii International Conference on System Sciences, 1999.

    Tuomi, Ilkka. 1999. "Data Is More than Knowledge: Implications of the Reversed Knowledge Hierarchy for Knowledge Management and Organizational Memory." Journal of Management Information Systems 16, no. 3 (1999): 103-17. http://www.jstor.org/stable/40398446.

    Van der Veer Martens, Betsy. 2015. "An Illustrated Introduction to the Infosphere". Library Trends 63, no. 3: 317-61.

    Wallace, Danny. 2005. "DIKW". Accessed 1/27/2017. http://listserv.utk.edu/cgi-bin/wa?A2=ind0512&L=jesse&T=0&X=0CF5BF3EF0390CDC08&P=1733.

    Weinberger, David. 2010. "The Problem with the Data-Information-Knowledge-Wisdom Hierarchy". Harvard Business Review Blog. Accessed 1/23/2017. https://hbr.org/2010/02/data-is-to-info-as-info-is-not.

    Williams, David. 2014. "Models, Metaphors and Symbols for Information and Knowledge Systems". Journal of Entrepreneurship Management and Innovation 10, no. 1: 79-107.

    Yu, Liangzhi. 2015. "Back to the Fundamentals Again: A Redefinition of Information and Associated LIS Concepts following a Deductive Approach". Journal of Documentation 71, no. 4: 795-816.

    Zeleny, Milan. 1987. "Management Support Systems: Towards Integrated Knowledge Management". Human Systems Management 7, no. 1: 59–70.

    Zins, Chaim. 2007. "Conceptual Approaches for Defining Data, Information, and Knowledge". Journal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology 58, no. 4: 479-93. doi: doi:10.1002/asi.20508.

    [top of entry]

     

    Visited Hit Counter by Digits times since 2018-06-07 (first publication).


    Version 1.0; published 2018-06-07, last edited 2022-02-09
    Article category: Theoretical concepts

    - <->This article (version 1.0) is also published in Knowledge Organization. How to cite it:
    Frické, Martin. 2019. “The knowledge pyramid: the DIKW hierarchy”. Knowledge Organization 49, no. 1: 33-46. Also available in ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization, eds. Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli, https://www.isko.org/cyclo/dikw

    ©2018 ISKO. All rights reserved.