I S K O

edited by Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli

 

Integrative levels

by Michael Kleineberg

Table of contents:
1. Introduction
2. A short history of an idea
    2.1 The Great Chain of Being
    2.2 Evolutionary order
    2.3 Levels of reality
    2.4 Integrative levels
3. Integrative levels as organizing principle
    3.1 Principles of organization
    3.2 Hierarchies and order relations
    3.3 The problem of transitivity
    3.4 Evaluation of level sequences
4. Common criticisms
    4.1 Hierarchy and formal logic
    4.2 Picture theory of meaning and universality claim
    4.3 Teleology and value ranking
5. Fields of application
    5.1 Interdisciplinary knowledge organization
    5.2 Semantic information retrieval
    5.3 Comparative method
    5.4 Viewpoint analysis and indexing
6. Conclusion
Acknowledgments
References
Appendix A: Sample of sequences based on the idea of integrative levels
Appendix B: Sample of conceptions of integrative levels
Appendix C: Sample of conceptions of integrative levels of knowing

Abstract:
This article provides a historical overview and conceptual clarification of the idea of integrative levels as an organizing principle. It will be demonstrated that this concept has found different articulations (e.g., levels of integration, levels of organization, levels of complexity, levels of granularity, nested hierarchy, specification hierarchy, hierarchical integration, progressive integration, holarchy, superformation, self-organization cycles) and widespread applications based on various, often unrelated theoretical and disciplinary backgrounds. In order to determine its role in the field of knowledge organization, some common misconceptions and major criticisms will be reconsidered in light of a broader multidisciplinary context. In particular, it will be shown how this organizing principle has been fruitfully applied to human-related research areas such as psychology, social sciences, or humanities in terms of integrative levels of knowing.

1. Introduction

In the field of knowledge organization, the organizing principle of integrative levels has a substantial though not uncontested tradition. The term "integrative levels" was first introduced in the late 1950s by the Classification Research Group (CRG) referring particularly to biochemist and sinologist Joseph Needham (1937), who invented this term, and philosopher James Feibleman (1954), who provided some generalizations or laws of the levels (Vickery 1958; Foskett 1961; 1962). Concerned with the determination of a scientifically justified sequence of main classes for a general classification scheme, Douglas Foskett (1961, 139) expressed the idea as follows:

The theory of integrative levels is that the world of things evolves from the simple towards the complex by an accumulation of properties, and that, at a succession of levels, these aggregations reach new degrees of complexity and become new wholes, with individual and unique identities.

Accordingly, integrative levels can be defined as a developmental sequence in which entities at each new level integrate the essential properties and structures of the entities at the older levels, while they exhibit some emergent qualities and, therefore, more complexity than their predecessors. A typical example of such a hierarchical order is presented by the sequence atoms—molecules—cells—organisms (Feibleman 1954, 62).

In more recent knowledge organization discourse, other authors emphasize other authorities who offer more or less independently developed but quite similar level conceptions. For example, Ingetraut Dahlberg (1974; 2008) as well as Claudio Gnoli and Roberto Poli (2004) rely on Nicolai Hartmann's concept of levels of reality that is based on two different kinds of hierarchical relations, namely, integrative levels called superformation and non-integrative levels called superposition, the latter without an accumulation of properties at each higher level. Furthermore, Søren Brier (2003) proposes the concept of levels of existence based on the co-evolution of matter and qualia inspired by Charles S. Peirce's evolutionary semiotics; Michael Kleineberg (2013) introduces Ken Wilber's concept of levels of being and knowing; and María López-Huertas (2013) discusses Basarab Nicolescu's concept of levels of reality and perception.

The history of the organizing principle of integrative levels, avant la lettre, can be traced back at least to the classifications of sciences by Herbert Spencer or Auguste Comte, which have influenced the work of many 19th and early 20th century classificationists or thesaurus constructors including, among others, Charles A. Cutter's Expansive Classification, Ernest C. Richardson's Order of the Sciences, James D. Brown's Subject Classification, Henry E. Bliss's Bibliographic Classification, and Peter M. Roget's Thesaurus of English Words and Phrases (Dousa 2009; Gnoli 2005, 2017). Since the time of the CRG, the concept of integrative levels has been discussed extensively and in the course of a profound critique of discipline-centered approaches explicitly applied in knowledge organization systems (KOSs) that are primarily oriented on phenomena or objects of being such as Kyle Classification (Kyle 1969), Information Coding Classification (Dahlberg 2008), → Integrative Levels Classification (Gnoli 2008), or → Basic Concepts Classification (Szostak 2012).

The strength of the idea of integrative levels is seen in its synthesizing force that enables a non-reductionist organization of the diversity of world phenomena based on logically coherent principles and a universal scope of coverage. As suggested by Foskett (1961), it provides a helpful framework for both the specialists systematizing their own subjects and the generalists identifying the interrelations of different research areas. Therefore, it is recommended as a theoretical foundation for interdisciplinary knowledge organization (ISKO Italy 2007; Szostak, Gnoli, and López-Huertas 2016). Additionally, the idea is proposed as a disambiguation tool for different meanings of core concepts like "information," "knowledge," "cognition," or "communication" and their related theoretical and methodological approaches (Fenzl et al. 1996; Brier 2003; Wilson 2003; Bates 2005; Gnoli and Ridi 2014); or by the same token, as a comparative tool for cross-cultural studies and the organization of the epistemological dimension of human knowledge (Kleineberg 2014).

On the other hand, the idea of integrative levels is challenged by internal and external criticisms. Internal criticisms are sympathetic with the level concept but point to some inconsistencies in proposed hierarchy models such as branchings and dead ends that seem to violate the linearity of the level sequence, as noted since early discussions (Feibleman 1954; Foskett 1961; Austin 1969c; Kyle 1969; Tomlinson 1969b). For example, Tomlinson (1969b) notes that the development from the level of molecules seems to branch into non-living phenomena (e.g., minerals, rocks) and living phenomena (e.g., cells, tissues). Moreover, there is some doubt that the organizing principle of integrative levels, which might work well for a hierarchical order of phenomena investigated in the natural sciences, can be fruitfully applied to those in the social sciences or humanities (Huckaby 1972; Langridge 1976; Spiteri 1995; Poli 2001; Dousa 2009). External criticisms, however, tend to reject the idea of integrative levels as such, for example, due to the presumptions of a reductionist logical class formation and oppressive hierarchical relations, an underlying picture theory of meaning and universal claims of validity, or a hidden teleology and an implicit value ranking (Olson 1999; Svenonius 2004; García Gutiérrez 2011).

The following sections are concerned with a historical overview of the idea of integrative levels, its utilization as an organizing principle for knowledge organization systems, a reconsideration of common criticisms, and an outline of major fields of application in knowledge organization research.

[top of entry]

2. A short history of an idea

2.1 The Great Chain of Being

The idea of integrative levels has a long history. Its origins are described in Arthur Lovejoy's (1936) The Great Chain of Being, a study that once established the discipline known as history of ideas by telling the story of one of the most influential ideas in Western history: the hierarchical order of reality. The genesis of this idea based on the principles of plenitude, continuity, and linear gradation, is traced back to ancient Greek philosophy, particularly to Plato's (1929, 2013) Timaeus and Republic, and its first full expression in the work of Aristotle. In Generation of Animals, Aristotle (1942) classifies animals according to their degree of perfection in eleven general grades from human beings at the top to so-called zoophytes at the bottom, an idea that will be later known as a single graded "scala naturae" (Lovejoy 1936, 58) — from Latin scala "ladder" or "staircase" of nature. Even more significant, Aristotle's (1935) On the Soul presents a hierarchical order of all living beings according to their powers of souls ranging from plants with nutritive power to human beings with rational power to possibly another even superior kind, with "each higher order possessing all the powers of those below it in the scale and an additional differentiating one of its own" (Lovejoy 1936, 58–59). In other words, this hierarchical order presents a historical precursor to the idea of integrative levels since each higher level integrates the essential properties of the lower levels, while adding something new.

According to Lovejoy (1936), the conception of the universe as a Great Chain of Being, exemplified in classical antiquity by Plotinus's (1992) Enneads and the Neoplatonist tradition taking the form of a hierarchical order from the supreme being of a godlike ens perfectissimum down to the meagerest kind of existents, was accepted by most philosophers and scientists without question during medieval times and until the late 18th century. Even in non-Western cultures, particularly in the wisdom traditions of Hinduism, Judaism, Buddhism, Taoism, or Islam, ideas quite similar to the Great Chain of Being have been articulated (Smith [1976] 1992; Wilber 1993).

Influential representatives are, for example, Augustine of Hippo and Pseudo-Dionysius the Aeropagite who both are seeking to combine Neoplatonist and Christian thought. Pseudo-Dionysius is known for inventing the term hierarchia "hierarchy" — a neologism from Greek hieros "sacred" and arkhia "rule" — denoting an order set out by God as the expression of divine law and will (Pseudo-Dionysius 1987, 153):

In my opinion, a hierarchy is a sacred order, a state of understanding and an activity approximating as closely as possible to the divine.

He distinguishes a celestial (intelligible) and an ecclesiastical (sensible) hierarchy, each divided into a series of triads where the first member "contains the power of the lower two, and so on" (Wear and Dillon 2007, 57). In this way, the hierarchical order of the universe reflects the distinctions of powers from different ranks of angels down to rational souls to irrational souls to plants, and to soulless matter.

Within the Christian tradition represented, among others, by Albertus Magnus, Thomas Aquinas, or Baruch Spinoza, the most determinative and pervasive version of the Great Chain of Being, according to Lovejoy (1936), is to be found in Gottfried W. Leibniz's ([1720] 2014) Monadology, in which he presents a hierarchical order from the divine at the top to human beings with rational souls to animals with non-rational souls down to simple substances or monads with lower perceptions. In order to solve the mind-body problem, Leibniz relies on the metaphysics of panpsychism, the assumption that all material entities have also a mind-like quality, and describes consequently his law of continuity stating that all properties attributed to a given level are integrated by each higher level in both physical and psychical terms, that is, as levels of being as well as "levels of consciousness" (Lovejoy 1936, 144).

[top of entry]

2.2 Evolutionary Order

During the 18th century, a "temporalizing of the Chain of Being" (Lovejoy 1936, 244) takes place as a reaction of paleontological findings and early evolutionary hypotheses that are questioning the idea of nature as a static order where every being finds its fixed and final god-given place. While the traditional order of emanationism descending from the most complex to the most simple is still to some extent echoed in the work of naturalists like Carl Linnaeus's (1758) Systema Naturae with its kingdoms of animals (e.g., mammals — birds — amphibians — fishes — insects — worms), plants and minerals, or Charles Bonnet's The Contemplation of Nature (Anderson 1976), the new temporalized chain of being or scala naturae follows the evolutionary order ascending from the most simple to the most complex, as stressed, among others, by Jean-Baptiste de Lamarck ([1809] 1914, 128):

I do not hesitate to say, however, that our general classifications of animals up to the present have been in the inverse order from that followed by nature when bringing her living productions successively into existence.

Therefore, in his Zoological Philosophy, Lamarck ([1809] 1914, 131) proposes six "stages of organization" according to what he considers as natural order and its progress of complexity (e.g., polyps — worms — insects — mollusks — fishes and reptiles — birds and mammals).

This kind of inversion and dynamization of the hierarchy reflects the Zeitgeist at the end of the 18th century in which various classification schemes in the natural sciences and also in academic libraries move human beings from the beginning to the end of the sequence (Šamurin [1955] 1977). Among philosophers, this turn becomes obvious if one compares, for example, Nicolas de Condorcet's essay Example des méthodes techniques that is concerned with classification theory and still represents more or less the old "reverse order" (Whitrow 1985, 92), with the new progressive order articulated in Johann G. Herder's Outlines of a Philosophy of the History of Man (1800, 108, emphasis his):

The more elaborate the organization of a creature is, the more its structure is compounded from the inferiour kingdoms. This complexedness begins underneath the earth, and grows up through plants and animals to the most complicated of all creatures, man.

In German idealism, the idea of a hierarchical order of reality is further elaborated, again in terms of both levels of being in the philosophy of nature as well as levels of knowing in the philosophy of mind or transcendental philosophy. In the attempt to combine both approaches, Friedrich W. J. Schelling's ([1800] 1978, 125–26) System of Transcendental Idealism describes the "scale of organization" simultaneously as "orders of intuition" culminating in absolute abstraction and the self-determination of intelligence. Based on the same dialectics of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, the idea of integrative levels is foreshadowed in Georg F. Hegel's ([1830] 1970, 20, emphasis his) Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences:

Nature is to be regarded as a system of stages, one arising necessarily from the other and being the proximate truth of the stage from which it results: but it is not generated naturally out of the other but only in the inner Idea which constitutes the ground of Nature.

This kind of speculative thought is overcome by more empirical explanations, particularly in evolutionary biology during the 19th century, a period known for celebrating the notions of evolution, development, and progress (Blitz 1992).

One of the most influential approaches is presented by Auguste Comte's ([1830-42] 1974) Course in Positive Philosophy in which he offers a two-sided strategy for the classification of human knowledge based on the idea of both levels of being as well as levels of knowing. Comte rejects the Baconian tradition of encyclopedic ladders of knowledge that is oriented on the faculties of human mind like memory, reason, or imagination because human understanding, for him, employs all of them more or less simultaneously. Instead, he proposes a hierarchy of fundamental sciences (e.g., astronomy — physics — chemistry — physiology — sociology) corresponding to the investigated objects or phenomena that are arranged according to their affiliation (Comte [1830-42] 1974, 53):

The order is determined by the degree of simplicity, or what amounts to the same thing, of generality in the phenomena, resulting in successive dependencies and consequently greater or less difficulty in study.

Additionally, Comte's famous law of three stages regarding the development of the human mind states that each branch of knowledge develops through a necessary order of three phases from a theological state to a metaphysical state up to a positive state, even though these developments do not need to take place synchronously and allow the coexistence of different states at the same time within a society. Moreover, Comte ([1830-42] 1974, 21) claims that since the starting point for both individual and collective education is necessarily the same "the principal phases of the individual represent the epochs of the species."

Inspired by Comte's work and contemporary Darwinian thought, Herbert Spencer's ([1862] 1915, 246) First Principles presents an all-inclusive concept of evolution covering astronomical, geological, biological, psychological, and sociological phenomena in terms of a "progressive integration of Matter" (e.g., inorganic — organic — super-organic) which means an increase in structural complexity from an indefinite and incoherent homogeneity to a definite and coherent heterogeneity.

[top of entry]

2.3 Levels of reality

In the late 19th and early 20th centuries, the idea of integrative levels finds widespread application in various research fields and is often discussed under the label "levels of reality," for example, within the discourse on emergent evolution among scholars like Conwy Lloyd Morgan, Samuel Alexander, C. D. Broad, William M. Wheeler, or Roy W. Sellars (Blitz 1992). According to David Blitz (1992), most approaches agree about at least three main levels of reality that can be summarized as matter — life — mind, whereas some argue for a preceding level of space-time and some for a succeeding level of society or even deity.

Arguably the most comprehensive and most detailed analysis of levels of reality is offered by Nicolai Hartmann's (1940) Der Aufbau der realen Welt (The structure of the real world) in which he introduces the hierarchical sequence of matter — life — psyche — spirit, the latter as the tripartite but inextricable unity of personal (individual), objective (collective), and objectivated (materialized in artifacts) spirit. Hartmann rejects the principle of continuity and restricts the scope of the idea of integrative levels, which he calls superformation (Überformung), to the levels of matter and life, while introducing the idea of superposition (Überbauung) where the higher level depends on the lower level but without integrating its essential properties. Most importantly, in his analysis two fundamental border lines between categorically orthogonal domains are identified, namely, a psychophysical border line between exterior life and interior psyche, and a border line between the individual personal spirit and the collective objective spirit (Kleineberg 2016).

Nevertheless, some authors defend the principle of continuity and, therefore, the integrative character of levels of reality by interpreting these border lines as boundaries between co-evolutionary correlates rather than emergent levels. For example, Morgan (1923, 26) maintains the view that through all levels of reality from matter to life to mind both exterior physical and interior psychical dimensions develop simultaneously:

This means, for me, that there are no physical systems, of integral status, that are not also psychical systems; and no psychical systems that are not also physical systems. All systems of events are in their degree psycho-physical.

Corresponding to such a panpsychism, Wheeler (1928, 39) proposes a kind of pansociality assuming different degrees of the social along all levels of reality in the sense of a co-evolution of the individual and collective dimensions: "Indeed, the correlations of the social — using the term in its most general sense — even extend down through the inorganic realm [...]."

A further important aspect of the idea of integrative levels is stressed by Wilhelm Dilthey's ([1910] 2002) The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences in which he compares the natural order investigated by the sciences with a reconstructed historical order studied by the humanities with the goal to defend a nomothetic approach to the latter. Inspired by Hegel while rejecting his metaphysics, Dilthey ([1910] 2002, 351, 184) is concerned with a critique of historical reason by analyzing the structure and development of human thought, for example, in terms of universal "stages of consciousness" or "stages of historical intelligibility." The importance of such an idea of integrative levels of knowing for human-related research fields is also emphasized, among others, by James M. Baldwin's (1906) Thought and Things, Wilhelm Wundt's ([1912] 1916) Elements of Folk Psychology, Ernst Cassirer's ([1923] 1955) Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, Max Scheler's ([1924] 1980) Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge, Norbert Elias's ([1939] 1994) The Civilizing Process, and Gaston Bachelard's ([1940] 1968) The Philosophy of No (see also Appendix C).

[top of entry]

2.4 Integrative levels

To some extent independent from the sketched history, Joseph Needham invents the term "integrative levels" for an idea that is outlined in his famous Herbert Spencer lecture Integrative Levels: A Revaluation of the Idea of Progress in the sense of "successive forms of order in a scale of complexity and organization" (Needham 1937, 3–4) that cover the whole known universe and the way in which it has come into being from the inorganic to the biological to the social. What is a whole at the lower and older level becomes a part at the next higher and newer level (e.g., protein crystals — cells — metazoan organisms — social units). In this way and with reference to Karl Marx's and Frederick Engels's materialist version of Hegelian dialectic, he also suggests different levels of integration within the social order in terms of both productive forces (basis) as well as cultural and cognitive aspects (superstructure).

A major contribution is achieved by James Feibleman's (1954) essay Theory of Integrative Levels in which thoughts by Joseph Needham, Ludwig Bertalanffy, or Alex Novikoff are systemized into a dozen laws of the levels (excerpted from 1954, 59–63):

  1. Each level organises the level or levels below it plus one emergent quality.
  2. Complexity of the levels increases upward.
  3. In any organisation the higher level depends upon the lower.
  4. In any organisation, the lower level is directed by the higher.
  5. For an organisation at any given level, its mechanism lies at the level below and its purpose at the level above.
  6. A disturbance introduced into an organisation at any one level reverberates at all the levels it covers.
  7. The time required for a change in organisation shortens as we ascend the levels.
  8. The higher the level, the smaller its population of instances.
  9. It is impossible to reduce the higher level to the lower.
  10. An organisation at any level is a distortion of the level below.
  11. Events at any given level affect organisations at other levels.
  12. Whatever is affected as an organisation has some effect as an organisation.

At the same time, Feibleman argues for a revision of the linearity of the level sequence due to occurring branchings and dead ends. For example, the development from the level of molecules seems to branch into both biological phenomena with increase of complexity as well as astronomical phenomena without increase of complexity.

As already mentioned, alternatives to strict linear sequences of integrative levels are also proposed by approaches that emphasize the notion of co-evolution of different categorically orthogonal domains. Some theorists argue for a co-evolution of the physical and the psychical in the broadest sense (Morgan 1923; Brier 2003), some others for a simultaneous emergence of the psychical and the social from the physical including the biological (Emmeche, Køppe, and Stjernfelt 1997; Poli 2001), again others even for interrelated developments of the physical, the psychical, and the social (Wheeler 1928; Wilber [1995] 2000; Kleineberg 2016). In particular, there are good reasons to assume a multi-leveled co-evolution of brain, cognition, and culture (Deacon 1997; Greenberg et al. 1999; Donald 2001), of material society and immaterial culture (Habermas 1979; Dux [2000] 2011), or of microsystems (e.g., atom — molecule — cell — complex organism) and macrosystems (e.g., star — planet — ecosystem — population) (Jantsch [1979] 1980; Wilber [1995] 2000).

After all, there seems to be no consensus on the idea of integrative levels, neither on the conceptual definition and theoretical foundation nor on the sequence and architecture of level models (Wheeler 1928; Greenberg and Kenyon 1987; Poli 2001). As a matter of fact, its utilization as organizing principle often reveals inconsistencies or exceptions for practical reasons (Spiteri 1995; Dousa 2009). Nevertheless, the theoretical interest in the idea of integrative levels continues until today, even though many domain-specific discourses appear to be isolated from each other using different terminologies within different more or less restricted fields of research (Yao 2009, see also Appendix B). These include, without claiming comprehensiveness, biology (Kummer 1987; Lobo 2008), ecology (Rowe 1961; Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman 2009), comparative psychology (Tobach 1987; Campbell 1990; Pisula 2009; Tomasello 2014), developmental psychology (Overton 2006; Commons 2008; Lourenço 2016), neuropsychology (Feinberg 2011), neuroanthropology (Deacon 1997; Donald 2001), social anthropology (Hallpike 2008), cognitive archaeology (Mithen 1996; Trigger 2003), macrosociology (Steward 1972; Nolan and Lenski 2015), sociocultural evolution (Sahlins and Service [1960] 1988; Habermas 1979; Dux [2000] 2011), general systems theory (Bertalanffy 1968), self-organization (Jantsch [1979] 1980; Fenzl et al. 1996), emergentism (Blitz 1992; Pettersson 1996; Bunge 2003), and hierarchy theory (Koestler 1967; Salthe 2009).

[top of entry]

Integrative levels as organizing principle

3.1 Principles of organization

Knowledge organization systems require organizing principles. Mathematician and library scientist Shiyali R. Ranganathan (1937, 183) specifies the following eight principles of organization for helpful sequences: later-in-time, later-in-evolution, spatial contiguity, quantitative measure, increasing complexity, canonical sequence, literary warrant, and alphabetical sequence. One advantage of the idea of integrative levels might be seen in its ability to combine several of these principles, namely, the relations of later-in-time, later-in-evolution, and increasing complexity (cp. Gnoli 2017).

The principle of increasing complexity is reflected by Feibleman's (1954) first and second laws of the levels stating that integrative levels are cumulative upward in terms of both properties and structures, while adding an emergent quality at each higher level. In the case of cumulative properties, this principle is compatible, as suggested by Broughton (2008, 49), with Bliss's principle of gradation by specialty that following Comte describes a sequence from the most general to the most specific, also known as genus-species relation. In cases of cumulative structures, however, one might speak of the principle of successive parthood that describes an "organisation as itself a part of some higher and more complex organisation" (Feibleman 1954, 61), also known as part-whole relation. A corollary of the principle of increasing complexity is expressed in Feibleman's (1954) third law stating that each higher level depends upon the lower level(s) but not vice versa, a relation that could be labeled in Comtean terms as the principle of successive dependence (cp. Gnoli, Bosch, and Mazzocchi 2007). Furthermore, Feibleman's eighth law stating that the population of instances decreases with each higher level (e.g., there exist fewer molecules than atoms, and fewer cells than molecules) could be termed the principle of decreasing span in correspondence with the principle of increasing depth, adopting Arthur Koestler's (1967, 342) terminology of "depth" (here a synonym for height or altitude) as the number of levels that an entity comprises and "span" as the number of entities at a given level. Since levels of integration are supposed to constitute evolutionary or developmental stages (Needham 1937; Feibleman 1954; Aronson 1987; Salthe 1991), it follows that they are also in line with Ranganathan's principle of later-in-evolution which in turn implies the principle of later-in-time, also expressed by Austin's (1969b, 114) "principle of consecutiveness."

Note that the two main principles of increasing complexity and later-in-evolution seem not to be reducible to each other. On one hand, not every order of complexity presents an evolutionary or diachronic sequence of entities but sometimes a rather synchronic one (e.g., tissue — organ — organism) that comes into being concurrently. For that reason, Austin (1969c, 88) rephrases Feibleman's fifth law:

For an organisation at any given sublevel [for Austin a "sublevel" means a part of a whole but not itself a whole, M.K.], its mechanism lies at the level below the whole of which it is a part, and its purpose is defined by a need of the whole of which it is a part.

On the other hand, not every evolutionary or developmental change means a change toward increasing complexity (e.g., a new species of bacteria). This is why Wilber (2000, 66) emphasizes the distinction between "translation" and "transformation", echoed by Overton's (2006, 25) distinction between "variational change" and "transformational change," according to which only the latter leads to an emergence of novelty and increasing complexity.

There might be other principles of organization that are compatible with the idea of integrative levels but one should carefully analyze to what extent these are constitutive. For example, Jolley (1973, 72) speaks of a "dimensional fallacy" for the tendency to consider aggregates like gross material bodies with an increase in the spatial dimension as increasingly higher levels of integration. Not to mention that the spatial dimension applies exclusively to material structures but not at all to mental structures (Richmond 1965; Kyle 1969). Another popular candidate is a sequence of increasing value (cp. Gnoli 2015), as exemplified by the historical idea of the Great Chain of Being in terms of an approximation to God stating that an increasing height of levels reflects an increasing godlikeness and value (Scrivner 1980). Such value rankings, however, appear to be rather accidental since integrative levels can be equally described in non-evaluative terms. For example, one can acknowledge that human beings are more complex and belong to a higher level than other life-forms without claiming that they are normatively superior or have more intrinsic value (Conger 1925; Aronson 1987).

In short, the organizing principle of integrative levels in a proper sense can be expressed in terms of evolutionary order based on the combined principles of gradation by specialty (genus-species relation), successive parthood (part-whole relation), and later-in-evolution (developmental relation) presenting "a conceptual progress from the general to the specific, the simple to the complex, and the past to the present" (Dousa 2009, 76).

In order to illustrate these inherent relations, various diagrammatic models and metaphors are in use evoking notions like "lower" and "higher", or "deeper" and "shallower" such as a nest or a spiral, a pyramid or a staircase, a chain or a ladder, each emphasizing certain aspects at the expense of some others (see Figure 1).

Figure 1: Metaphors for integrative levels as nest, pyramid, and chain

For example, similar to Russian dolls or Chinese boxes, a nesting of concentric circles depicts levels of integration in a way that each level as a whole is included as a part in the next more complex level, just as atoms are included in molecules which in turn are included in cells. This two-faced aspect of a given level has been aptly called "holon" — from Greek holos "whole" and the suffix –on suggesting a part or particle like in proton or neutron — meaning a simultaneous whole and part relative to the view along the level hierarchy or "holarchy" (Koestler 1967, 48, 103).

In contrast, the same sequence of integrative levels can be illustrated by a pyramid where each higher level rests and depends on the more fundamental lower level(s), while the population of instances or the span decreases at each higher level, just as there are fewer molecules than atoms and fewer cells than molecules (cp. Feibleman 1954; Blitz 1992).

Another way to represent the same sequence of integrative levels is a simple chain that can be depicted horizontally or vertically with an increasing or decreasing sequence. In Figure 1, the chain is reproduced vertically as inverse sequence of the pyramid beginning with the most fundamental and most general level at the top in order to illustrate that it constitutes the root class of a "specification hierarchy" (Salthe 2009, 87) in which each sub-class presents a specification of the preceding more general class, just as the physical level (e.g., atomic matter) is specified by the chemical level (e.g., molecular matter) which in turn is specified by the biological level (e.g., cellular matter) without claiming that one of them can be reduced to any other.

While it seems to be true that the idea of integrative levels is compatible with a broad range of well-known principles of organization, it appears to be equally true that different aspects are often combined without sufficient qualification which might lead to serious inconsistencies in modeling hierarchical sequences of integrative levels.

[top of entry]

3.2 Hierarchies and order relations

The idea of integrative levels is the idea of a hierarchy. In the field of knowledge organization, hierarchies are considered to be one of the most informationally rich and most effective semantic relations for the development of knowledge organization systems like classifications, thesauri, or formal ontologies (Svenonius 2000; Stock and Stock 2013; → Frické 2016; Gnoli 2017). Most importantly, hierarchical relations, in opposition to equivalence relations or association relations, are able to represent an order in the mathematical sense (Stock and Stock 2013).

Order theory is the branch of mathematics that is concerned with the formalization of the intuitive notion of ranking using binary relations for a comparison of pairs of objects. Order relations rest on the properties of transitivity and antisymmetry, while they can be strict or non-strict (Davey and Priestley 2008). A non-strict order (or non-strict partial order) on a set is a binary relation ≤ on this set such that, for all its elements x, y, z:

(a) x ≤ x (reflexivity),
(b) x ≤ y and y ≤ x imply x = y (antisymmetry),
(c) x ≤ y and y ≤ z imply x ≤ z (transitivity).

Every relation ≤ induces a relation < of strict inequality in the way that x < y if and only if x ≤ y and x ≠ y. Therefore, it is possible to restate the conditions (a)–(c) in terms of a strict order (or strict partial order) on a set which is a binary relation < on this set such that, for all its elements x, y, z:

(a) x < x does not hold (irreflexivity),
(b) if x < y then y < x does not hold (asymmetry),
(c) x < y and y < z imply x < z (transitivity).

Note that irreflexivity and transitivity combined already imply asymmetry which in turn is defined by antisymmetry and irreflexivity.

While mathematicians usually allow equality as it is implicit in the non-strict order relation less-than-or-equal-to or its opposite greater-than-or-equal-to, outside mathematics the strict order relation less-than or its opposite greater-than is much more common and can be regarded as equally fundamental (Davey and Priestley 2008). In knowledge organization literature, hierarchical relations are described in terms of both non-strict orders (Jolley 1973; Svenonius 2000) and strict orders (Jolley 1973; Stock and Stock 2013; Gnoli 2017), depending on the interpretation of the condition of reflexivity or irreflexivity.

However, this distinction becomes crucial for the concept of levels of integration that is based on two main assumptions. First, there are qualitatively distinct levels that can be ranked in a linear developmental sequence from the less complex to the more complex. Second, there are hierarchical integrations in the way that each more complex level includes the essential structures and properties of its predecessors. In connection with conceptual ordering systems like knowledge organization systems, the question arises whether or not hierarchical relations are non-strict orders that hold reflexivity, meaning that a given set (e.g., a class, a concept, a term, a level) would include itself as its own subset (e.g., a subclass, a subordinate concept, a narrower term, a lower level). According to the idea of integrative levels this seems not to be the case since a given level integrates a lower level while adding something new (Feibleman's first law). This process is often described in terms of differentiation and integration, or transcendence and inclusion (Spencer [1862] 1915; Salthe 1991; Wilber [1995] 2000; Lourenço 2016). Hence a level and its next lower level cannot be identical and their relation of inclusion is an irreflexive one. This leads to the conclusion that the hierarchical relation of integrative levels is a strict linear order exhibiting the properties of irreflexivity, asymmetry, and transitivity.

[top of entry]

3.3 The problem of transitivity

While it appears to be quite obvious that the modeling of integrative levels requires an asymmetric relation, because if one level is integrated by another, then the opposite cannot be true (e.g., atoms are integrated by molecules, but molecules are not integrated by atoms), it seems to be much more difficult to meet the condition of a transitive relation. It goes without saying that the principles of organization identified above as being constitutive for integrative levels (i.e., increasing complexity, gradation by specialty, successive parthood, successive dependence, decreasing span, increasing depth, later-in-evolution, later-in-time) are supposed to be transitive relations. But as often noted, transitivity requires a homogeneous way of subdivision along the hierarchy, a requirement that seems to be frequently violated at the price of inconsistent relations of inclusion (Beghtol 2000; Svenonius 2000; Guizzardi 2009; Stock and Stock 2013; Almeida and Baracho 2014). Therefore, it is of utmost importance for the idea of integrative levels to qualify different types of subdivisions.

In this regard, a first basic distinction is usually made between genus-species relations based on → logical division and part-whole relations based on structural or partitive division (Frické 2016), also known by the following terminological distinctions: is-a-kind-of relation vs. is-a-part-of relation (Stock and Stock 2013, 554, 555), generic relation vs. partitive relation (Broughton et al. 2005, 144), class inclusion vs. merological inclusion (Winston, Chaffin, and Herrmann 1987, 435), hyponym-hyperonym relation vs. meronym-holonym relation (Stock and Stock 2013, 552, 555), specification hierarchy vs. scale hierarchy (Salthe 1991, 260), subsumptive hierarchy vs. compositional hierarchy (Salthe 2009, 88), or taxonomy vs. partonomy (Beghtol 2000, 315). On one hand, a genus-species relation can be defined by a concept and its subordinated concept that inherits all properties attributed to its superordinated concept. On the other hand, a part-whole relation can be defined by an item and its superordinated item that integrates the structure or organization of its subordinated item as an integral part (Stock and Stock 2013; Frické 2016). As stressed by Beghtol (2000), both types of subdivision are often combined within the same KOS and the failure to distinguish them encourages ambiguity since the same set of foci (e.g., heart, liver, lungs) can be interpreted in terms of both a genus-species facet (e.g., kind of organs) or a part-whole facet (e.g., parts of bodies).

Since for the idea of integrative levels both genus-species relations and part-whole relations are constitutive, it follows that both types of hierarchical subdivision need to be applied simultaneously and each one of them must exhibit transitivity. For example, the sequence atom — molecule — cell can be interpreted at the same time as both a genus-species hierarchy (e.g., kinds of matter) and a part-whole hierarchy (e.g., parts of organisms).

Moreover, there exist different types of subdivisions within each of these two main hierarchical relations. On one hand, the genus-species relation can be qualified in the following way (based on Chaffin and Hermann cited in Beghtol 2000, 314):

Genus-species relations
Perceptual subordination (e.g., animal — horse)
Functional subordination (e.g., furniture — chair)
State subordination (e.g., disease — polio)
Activity subordination (e.g., game — chess)
Geographic subordination (e.g., state — New Jersey).

As noted by Stock and Stock (2013), it is important for an is-a-kind-of relation that the subordinated concept (hyponym) and the superordinated concept (hyperonym) are regarded from the same perspective and that not every is-a relation (simple hyponomy) is necessarily an is-a-kind-of relation (taxonomy) which per definitionem entails a transitive sequence. For example, it appears to be inappropriate to say that a stallion is-a-kind-of instead of is-a horse because a stallion is regarded from the perspective of gender and a horse is not (Cruse 2002).

From a logical point of view, it must also be emphasized that even if nearly all definitions in natural-language dictionaries refer to a genus-species relation (Svenonius 2000), the order-theoretical property of transitivity does not necessarily apply in ordinary language contexts that rely on less formal principles, like Ludwig Wittgenstein's family resemblance stating that not all but only a few properties attributed to a class need to be inherited by its subclass, or Eleanor Rosch's prototype theory stating that categorization is graded and some subclasses are more central than others (Stock and Stock 2013; → Frické 2016; → Hjørland 2017).

On the other hand, the part-whole relation can be qualified as follows (based on Winston, Chaffin, and Herrmann 1987, 420; see also Stock and Stock 2013; Almeida and Baracho 2014):

Part-whole relations
Component — integral object (e.g., pedal — bike)
Member — collection (e.g., ship — fleet)
Portion — mass (e.g., slice — pie)
Stuff — object (e.g., steel — car)
Feature — activity (e.g., paying — shopping)
Place — area (e.g., Everglades — Florida).

Again, the problem of transitivity occurs if different types of subdivision are combined within the same hierarchical sequence or stated in the premises of a syllogism (Cruse 1979; Winston, Chaffin, and Herrmann 1987; Guizzardi 2009; Almeida and Baracho 2014). This seems to be of particular importance for KOSs like formal ontologies that enable automated reasoning in order to enhance information retrieval. The following example presents an intransitive part-whole relation and, therefore, an invalid conclusion (based on Winston, Chaffin, and Herrmann 1987, 431–32):

Premises:Simpson's arm is part (component) of Simpson.
Simpson is part (member) of the Philosophy department.
Conclusion:Simpson's arm is part (?) of the Philosophy department.

In other words, for modeling integrative levels the condition of transitivity is by far the most important challenge and, at the same time, the most important evaluation criterion for the consistency of proposed hierarchical sequences.

[top of entry]

3.4 Evaluation of level sequences

In this section, some exemplary sequences based on the idea of integrative levels will be reconsidered in light of the transitivity condition in order to identify typical cases of inconsistency (see also Appendix A):

(I) Atoms — molecules — cells — organisms — human beings — human societies (Coates 1969, 21).

As noted by Austin (1969c, 88), some authors add an "aggregative or societal level" beyond man, ignoring the fact that this violates the principle of later-in-evolution since collective human societies emerge concurrently with individual human beings. Furthermore, different part-whole relations seem to be confused since atoms, molecules, and cells are components of organisms, whereas human beings are members of human societies, just as all individual life-forms are members of their collective population or species. In general, Austin (1969c) concludes that such collective phenomena spring from that individual entity along the integrative levels sequence that forms the parts of the aggregate. Therefore, such alleged branchings are derived from the confusion of integration and aggregation leading to what one might call the individual/collective inconsistency.

(II) Atom — molecule — molecular assemblage — physical structure — planet — collection of planets — universe (Tomlinson 1969b, 30).

This level sequence presents a further version of the individual/collective inconsistency at the inorganic level. In contrast to the integrative relation between atom and molecule, the aggregative relations between molecule and molecular assemblage or between planet and a collection of planets do not present an increase in complexity but rather what Jolley (1973, 72) calls the spatial version of the "dimensional fallacy" (cp. Jantsch [1979] 1980; Wilber [1995] 2000).

Note that the entity "universe" at the end of the sequence in example (II) also violates the principle of later-in-evolution and should be replaced to the beginning since the existence of the universe starts from the Big Bang and does not depend on the emergence of the other mentioned entities. The same misconception, which one might call the consecutiveness inconsistency, holds if ecosystems or the biosphere are considered to be the highest and most complex level of living entities, as suggested by Rowe (1961) or Lobo (2008). Instead, it should be recognized that the biosphere comes into being concurrently with the first forms of life.

For the same reason, the anthroposphere or noosphere referring to human-related phenomena should not be considered to be integrated by a spatially greater biosphere but quite the opposite: the noosphere is a specification of the biosphere, while the biosphere is an integral part of the noosphere (Wilber 2000; Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman 2009).

(III) Physical entities — chemical entities — heterogenous non-living entities — artefacts — biological entities — man — mentefacts (CRG quoted in Austin 1969b, 112–3).

Another version of the consecutiveness inconsistency occurs if non-living human artifacts are placed before living entities since they depend on the emergence of human beings, as stressed by Austin (1969b) or Dahlberg (1974) relying on Feibleman's (1954, 64) rule that the "reference of any organisation must be to the highest level which its explanation requires."

(IV) Physical — chemical — biological — psychological — cultural (Feibleman 1954, 63).

This level sequence seems to be challenged by Hartmann's (1940) psychophysical border line between the biological and the psychological that violates both the principle of gradation by specialty and the principle of successive parthood since biological properties or structures (e.g., spatial exteriority, cellular structure) are not integrated by the psychological level (e.g., non-spatial interiority, cognitive structure).

One way to avoid such a categorical mistake, which one might call the exterior/interior inconsistency, is to adopt a pure materialist approach, as preferred by Austin (1969c, 88) who restricts the number of levels to not more than four "truly integrative" ones: fundamental particles — elements — compounds — living compounds. In fact, there is a long tradition of materialism which appears to be strongly reductionist in that it does not take psychical or cultural phenomena into account (Novikoff 1945; Rowe 1961; Jolley 1973; Pettersson 1996; Bunge 2003; Vickery 2005).

Any non-reductionist approach, however, needs to consider some categorically orthogonal domains that cannot be arranged linearly as a transitive sequence due to the lack of hierarchical inclusions, as indicated by Poli's (2001) three domains of the material, the mental, and the social; or Wilber's ([1995] 2000) four domains of the objective, the subjective, the intersubjective, and the interobjective (Kleineberg 2016). In principle, there seem to be two different strategies to deal with that challenge: either the linearity of the level sequence will be defended at the price of hierarchical inclusions or the hierarchical inclusions of the level sequence will be defended at the price of linearity.

The first strategy is adopted, to some extent, by Hartmann's (1940) conception of levels of reality. In this tradition, the idea of levels of integration is replaced by the more general notion of "level of organization" (Gnoli 2017, 40) stating that each higher level depends historically and logically on the next lower level but without a mandatory integration of its essential structures and properties. In other words, while the principle of later-in-evolution still holds, the principles of successive parthood and gradation by specialty do not.

The second strategy is mostly elaborated by Wilber's ([1995] 2000) conception of co-evolutionary holons. In this school of thought, the idea of integrative levels is maintained but the linear sequence is modified in the way that categorically orthogonal domains are related as interdependent and co-evolutionary correlates (see Table 1).

Table 1: Emergent integrative levels and co-evolutionary correlates
Integrative levels Correlates:
Exterior-individual
(objective)
 
Interior-individual
(subjective)
 
Exterior-collective
(interobjective)
 
Interior-collective
(intersubjective)
Examples
1. Matter ? ? ? Atom
2. Complex matter ? ? ? Molecule
3. Life ? ? ? Cell
4. Complex life Proto-mind Proto-society Proto-culture Organism
5. Most complex life Mind Society Culture Human being

In order to compare and evaluate proposed sequences of integrative levels, Table 1 presents a framework that avoids both the individual/collective and the exterior/interior inconsistencies by distinguishing emergent integrative levels and co-evolutionary correlates with regard to a widely agreed-upon example sequence. Transitivity of integrative levels applies within each column, even though the origins of the evolutionary proto-forms for the anthropocentric phenomena of mind, society, and culture might be located differently and must, for the time being, remain open questions (Kleineberg 2016).

From that perspective, a last level sequence that is quite typical for the field of knowledge organization, taken from the research project Integrative Levels Classification, will be reconsidered:

(V) Forms — matter — life — mind — society — culture (Gnoli 2017, 46).

Although inspired by the idea of integrative levels, this hierarchical sequence relies much more on Hartmann's notion of superposition without mandatory hierarchical inclusions. Leaving aside the domain of forms whose ontological status seems to be controversial, as the author admits, this linear sequence can easily be mapped onto the emergent-correlate framework. In this way, it might become more evident to what extent relations between entities or concepts constitute integrative levels or superformation within a column (e.g., matter — life), non-integrative levels or superposition across columns (e.g., life — mind), or co-evolutionary correlates within a row (e.g., mind — society — culture) (see also Table 2).

Table 2: Principles of organization
Order relation Integrative levels
(superformation)
Non-integrative levels
(superposition)
Correlates
(co-evolution)
Increasing complexity Yes ? ?
Gradation by specialty Yes No No
Successive parthood Yes No No
Successive dependence Yes Yes Interdependence
Decreasing span Yes Yes No
Increasing depth Yes Yes No
Later-in-time Yes Yes No
Later-in-evolution Yes Yes No

[top of entry]

4. Common criticisms

4.1 Hierarchy and formal logic

The idea of integrative levels as an organizing principle is criticized on many grounds and still a matter of controversial debates. Most importantly, the limitations and shortcomings of the notion of hierarchy for conceptual ordering systems are emphasized, no matter whether hierarchical relations are taking generic, partitive, or developmental forms (Olson 1999; García Gutiérrez 2011; Mai 2011; De Beer 2015). According to Olson (1999), the predominant classificatory thought and practice is based on classical formal logic rooting in the Aristotelean tradition with the underlying and interrelated presumptions of disjoint class formation (exclusivity), a linear progression towards a goal (teleology), and a rigid subordination through logical division and the dominance of some classes over others (hierarchy). It is argued that this kind of classification presents a culture-specific construction and tends to oppress and marginalize alternative kinds of organizing knowledge (Olson 1999; Jacob 2000; García Gutiérrez 2011).

Therefore, the idea of a hierarchical order of reality is questioned with regard to its theoretical and metatheoretical assumptions, while often a change in metaphors is proposed from tree-like hierarchies to rhizome-like webs, that is, a shift in emphasis from hierarchical relations to associative relations (Robinson and Maguire 2010; López-Huertas 2013; De Beer 2015). In this regard, the traditional → classification based on formal logic is often contrasted with conceptual ordering systems that are more in line with Wittgenstein's notion of family resemblance or Rosch's prototype theory, which allow overlapping classes without essential properties and, therefore, the formation of intransitive hierarchical relations (Jacob 2004; Hjørland 2017). Some authors consider these approaches as "two complementary forms of representation" (Priss 2001, 53) and argue to overcome the reductionism of formal logic by means of a "wider and inclusive cognitive matrix" (García Gutiérrez 2011, 9) that does not deny the formal-logical way of thinking but seeks to integrate it into a logical pluralism.

From a developmental perspective, however, it should be noted that such a logical pluralism can itself be organized according to the principle of integrative levels in terms of "levels of knowing" (Wilber 1999, 451), "levels of consciousness" (Overton 2006, 53), "stages of thought" (Commons 2008, 305), or "levels of perception" (Nicolescu 2010, 25), while offering a clearer distinction between dominator hierarchies and growth hierarchies. For example, the Model of Hierarchical Complexity proposed by cognitive psychologist Michael Commons and colleagues (1998; 2008) present an invariant sequence of task performances understood as the activity of organizing information in which actions at a higher level coordinate and transform the lower-level actions. According to that framework, the use of classical formal logic is represented by four distinct levels from simple deductions to a full-fledged system of formal operations including Boolean operators, while seven preceding preformal levels and four succeeding postformal levels are distinguished. The latter metasystematic or metalogical kind of reasoning that integrates its precursors is also reflected, for example, by Wilber's ([1995] 2000, 266) "vision-logic," Overton's (2006, 32) "relational metatheory," and Nicolescu's (2010) "logic of the included middle."

[top of entry]

4.2 Picture theory of meaning and universality claim

Another criticism is concerned with the underlying epistemology of the classical theory of integrative levels. As Svenonius (2004) points out, Feibleman's approach seems to be based on a correspondence theory of truth in the way that his description of the level sequence is supposed to mirror the actual structure of external reality. This kind of a picture theory of meaning is criticized by context-sensitive instrumental or use theories of meaning for being objectivist, positivistic, and reductionist, while claiming universal validity regardless of alternative constructions of reality (Jacob 2000; Svenonius 2004; Mai 2011; → Hjørland 2017).

However, several approaches demonstrate that an acknowledgement of the context-dependent nature of human knowledge does not necessarily mean to give up the possibility of universal validity claims (for example, the claim that all human knowledge is context-dependent), and even less that a rejection of the picture theory of meaning implies a rejection of the idea of integrative levels (Bertalanffy 1968; Habermas 1979; Wilber [1995] 2000; Fenzl et al. 1996; Brier 2003; Overton 2006; Kleineberg 2013).

[top of entry]

4.3 Teleology and value ranking

According to Olson's (1999) critique, teleology within classification is illustrated by a linear progression of main classes from basic to more developed phenomena that is oriented toward a goal and implies a value ranking, as exemplified by Aristotle's hierarchical order of animals with human beings at the top level. Indeed, historical ideas like the Great Chain of Being clearly present hierarchies of value and many progress theories since the 18th century tend to make unjustified teleological assumptions, as prominently presented in the work of Teilhard de Chardin ([1955] 1959). But while recent theories of evolution commonly reject the idea of a "scala naturae," some authors argue for a modified version that avoids both teleology and value ranking (Greenberg 1995; Donald 2001).

As stressed by theories of self-organization, transformational change in evolution or development presents directionality without a telos, that is, increasing complexity without a final goal (Jantsch [1979] 1980; Aronson 1987; Wilber [1995] 2000; Brier 2003). Therefore, an adequate explanation requires a reconstruction after the fact and a clearer distinction between the dynamics and the logic of development (Habermas 1990).

With regard to integrative levels of knowing, there is a strong emphasis on the dialectics of progress that includes both a growth of learning abilities but also new problem situations and possible pathologies (Habermas 1979; Wilber 1999). Furthermore, it is underlined that normative approaches claiming a hierarchy of justification are able to avoid the naturalistic fallacy by taking recourse to philosophical arguments (Kohlberg and Hersh 1977; Habermas 1990; King and Kitchener 1994).

[top of entry]

5. Fields of application

5.1 Interdisciplinary knowledge organization

Since at least Comte's and Spencer's classifications of the sciences, the main motivation for the elaboration on the idea of integrative levels is to interrelate different domains of human knowledge according to a hierarchical order in terms of either discipline-centered fields of research or phenomena-centered objects under investigation, or even a combination of both within the same KOS such as the Bliss Bibliographic Classification, Second Edition (Gnoli 2005). According to Needham (1937), such a big picture is important as soon as researchers take the broader context of their special fields into account, while Feibleman (1954, 59) even speaks of a kind of "super-science" that is particularly concerned with the interrelations among disciplines like physics, chemistry, biology, psychology, and anthropology. Some theorists consider the idea of integrative levels promising for a defense of the unity of science (Oppenheimer and Putnam 1958; Reiser 1958; Bertalanffy 1968), while others argue for a transdisciplinary approach beyond disciplinary borders since "levels of organization offer the possibility of a new taxonomy of the more than 8000 academic disciplines existing today" (Nicolescu 2010, 27).

In the field of knowledge organization, this synthesizing aspect of the idea of integrative levels is recognized by the CRG and exploited for the development of a basic scheme of a new general classification that is based directly on phenomena maintaining a universal scope of coverage. As noted by Austin (1969a), due to academic overspecialization discipline-centered knowledge organization systems are challenged by the problems of keeping the scheme up to date (currency), inserting new subjects (hospitality), or avoiding multiple entries (cross-classification). In order to meet James E. Farradane's condition of a "place of unique definition" (Austin 1969b, 111), the CRG's new general classification adopts the organizing principle of integrative levels as a non-arbitrary linear order of phenomena or main classes which in turn can be combined by using the analytico-synthetic technique of faceted classification with fundamental categories or facets that indicate different kinds of relationships or particular semantic contexts (Gnoli 2008). Although the CRG's proposal never reached the status of practical application, similar approaches elaborated further such an interdisciplinary approach to knowledge organization. For example, Dahlberg's (2008) Information Coding Classification, developed in the 1970s, seeks to combine nine integrative levels of objects of being with nine facets in order to define a comprehensive matrix of discrete fields of knowledge or subject groups.

During the last decade, theorizing about phenomena-centered faceted classifications based on the organizing principle of integrative levels has been intensified and practically applied in KOSs like Basic Concepts Classification or Integrative Levels Classification (ISKO Italy 2007; Gnoli 2008; Szostak 2012; Kleineberg 2013; Gnoli 2017). In particular, the monograph Interdisciplinary Knowledge Organization (Szostak, Gnoli, and López-Huertas 2016) summarizes its potential benefits and expands the scope from classification to further types of KOSs like thesauri or formal ontologies.

[top of entry]

5.2 Semantic information retrieval

Knowledge organization systems serve information retrieval of relevant documents and in cases where documentary languages are machine-readable vocabularies, such as XML (Extensible Markup Language) based on RDF (Resource Description Framework) and formal ontologies (e.g., Suggested Upper Merged Ontology, General Formal Ontology), one is concerned with semantic information retrieval (Rajasurya et al. 2012). An advantage of such semantic web technologies is to enable automated reasoning based on a structured database of facts or RDF statements combined with documentary languages exhibiting transitive semantic relations (Guizzardi 2009; Herre 2013; Almeida and Baracho 2014; Santis and Gnoli 2016). As argued by D. Grant Campbell (2002), the framework of integrative levels could play a significant role in the integration of RDF statements into formal ontologies. Furthermore, information retrieval often uses automated query expansion by moving upwards in transitive concept ladders (Gnoli, Santis and Pusterla 2015), for example, from the smallest geographical unit to larger ones in order to detect the nearest location of interest (Stock and Stock 2013). In this regard, sequences of integrative levels due to their inherent multiple transitive order relations appear to be promising informationally rich tools.

[top of entry]

5.3 Comparative method

The idea of integrative levels offers a framework that allows comparison of different degrees of complexity within a given developmental sequence. In the broader inter- or transdisciplinary field of information research, the comparative method has been applied to disambiguate some basic concepts like "information," "knowledge," "cognition," or "communication" in order to interrelate different theoretical and methodological approaches (Fenzl et al. 1996; Hjørland 2002; Brier 2003; Wilson 2003; Bates 2005; Gnoli and Ridi 2014; Yao 2009). For example, Fenzl et al. (1996) propose a multi-level model of information based on a combined layer-theoretical (dialectic of whole and part) and phase-theoretical (dialectic of old and new) concept expressed as a hierarchical sequence from physico-chemical systems (dissipation) to biotic systems (autopoiesis) to socio-cultural systems (re-creation). Aiming toward a unified information theory, their hierarchy of cognition and communication is able to identify and delimitate the particular ontological level a given approach (e.g., Claude Shannon's theory of communication) is actually concerned with. One of the most comprehensive comparative frameworks, the Model of Hierarchical Complexity developed by Commons (2008) within the intersection of information science and developmental psychology, presents integrative levels of behavioral tasks accounting for both performances of machines and human action.

As noted by Wilson (2003), the idea of integrative levels is today widely employed in fields like biology, biochemistry, comparative psychology, and environmental science, and these already existing hierarchical sequences might provide useful semantic relations for the development of domain-specific KOSs (see Appendix A). In this regard, a major contribution is made by "incorporating the levels of consciousness into the framework of the integrative levels theory" (Pisula 2016, 51) since it offers comparative tools with regard to the evolution and development of human consciousness and the cognitive aspects of cultural artifacts and documents (Werner and Kaplan 1956; Haaften, Korthals, and Wren 1997; Greenberg et al. 1999; Quilley 2010; Oesterdiekhoff 2013). This seems to be of particular importance since in knowledge organization discourse, the concept of "mentefacts" (Kyle 1969, 14), that is, intellectual concepts and systems, appears to be theoretically underdeveloped and, therefore, fails in applying the organizing principle of integrative levels for the social sciences and humanities (Huckaby 1972; Langridge 1976; Spiteri 1995; Poli 2001; Dousa 2009).

[top of entry]

5.4 Viewpoint analysis and indexing

As argued by Kleineberg (2013; 2014), the application of the idea of integrative levels to the epistemological dimension of human knowledge offers an organizing principle for the plurality of different perspectives or viewpoints in terms of integrative levels of knowing (see Appendix C). According to developmental psychologist Orlando M. Lorenço (2016, 123 [emphases his]), this concept can be characterized by the following main criteria: "(a) Hierarchy: stages appear in an invariant, hierarchical order; (b) integration: a given stage integrates, albeit overcomes or transcends its predecessor." In the field of knowledge organization, this principle has been utilized for classifying the epistemic outlook of both creators and users of documents. On one hand, Jason Farradane's (1963) relational indexing is an early attempt to incorporate cognitive-developmental aspects, as analyzed by Jean Piaget and others, in order to indicate the degree of conceptual clarity that is represented in documents (see also Foskett 1980). On the other hand, Jihee Beak's (2014) child-driven metadata scheme uses such developmental level models of cognition for the analysis of particular user groups and the development of user-centered indexing languages.

In many other human-related research areas, the idea of integrative levels of knowing serves also as an organizing principle for a classification of the epistemological dimension in order to describe the "conceptual profiles" (Mortimer et al. 2014) that are embedded in artifacts or documents of the cultural and scientific heritage (Thompson 1996; Haaften, Korthals, and Wren 1997; Barnes 2000; Bammé 2011). This includes various domain-specific lines of cognitive development such as spatial representation in pictorial art (Gablik 1979), Paleolithic stone tool technology (Wynn 1985), narrative structures in English literature (LePan 1989), ethics in classical Chinese literature (Roetz 1993), symbolization in ancient Egyptian artifacts (Brunner-Traut 1996), arithmetics in ancient Sumerian-Babylonian texts (Damerow 1996), and religious systems in mythological and theological writings (Bellah 2011).

[top of entry]

6. Conclusion

Although not uncontested, the idea of integrative levels presents one of the most informationally rich organizing principles for conceptual ordering systems that combines several order relations, most importantly, gradation by specialty (genus-species hierarchy), successive parthood (part-whole hierarchy) and later-in-evolution (developmental hierarchy), even though these order relations are rarely made explicit but rather remain implicit assumptions.

In the field of knowledge organization, the idea of integrative levels has been applied either discipline-centered or phenomena-centered in both domain-specific and interdisciplinary knowledge organization systems including formal ontologies for semantic information retrieval. In this regard, the most important challenge is the condition of transitivity for its hierarchical relations that seems to be frequently violated not least due to a lack of conceptual consensus. Indeed, it would appear misleading to speak of "the" theory of integrative levels since there are various and often unrelated approaches grounded in different paradigms or disciplinary contexts. Knowledge organization research, however, might benefit from classification schemes based on the idea of integrative levels that already exist in other fields, in particular, from largely neglected developmental sequences reconstructed by psychology, social sciences and humanities.

[top of entry]

Acknowledgements

The author would like to thank the two anonymous reviewers and the editor, Birger Hjørland, for constructive criticism and helpful suggestions, Ann Graf for a careful proof-reading and feedback on the manuscript, and Claudio Gnoli for intensive discussions and inspiration.

References

Alexander, Samuel. [1920] 1950. Space, Time and Deity. London: Macmillan.

Almeida, Mauricio B., and Renata A. Baracho. 2014. "A Theoretical Investigation about the Notion of Parts and Wholes: Mereological and Meronymic Relations." Brazilian Journal of Information Science: Research Trends 8 (1/2). http://www2.marilia.unesp.br/revistas/index.php/bjis/article/view/4247/3086.

Anderson, Lorin. 1976. "Charles Bonnet's Taxonomy and Chain of Being." Journal of the History of Ideas 37 (1): 45–58.

Apel, Karl-Otto. 1978. "Transcendental Semiotics and the Paradigms of First Philosophy." Philosophic Exchange 9 (1): 3–22.

Aristotle. 1935. "On the Soul." In On the Soul. Parva Naturalia. On Breath, 2–203. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Aristotle. 1942. Generation of Animals. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Aronson, Lester R. 1987. "Some Remarks on Integrative Levels." In Cognition, Language and Consciousness: Integrative Levels, edited by Gary Greenberg and Ethel Tobach. Hillsdale: Erlbaum, 269–86.

Atran, Scott. 1990. Cognitive Foundation of Natural History: Towards an Anthropology of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Austin, Derek. 1969a. "Prospects for a New General Classification." Journal of Librarianship and Information Science 1 (3): 149–69.

Austin, Derek. 1969b. "Report to the Library Association Research Committee on the Use of the NATO Grant." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 110–24.

Austin, Derek. 1969c. "The Theory of Integrative Levels Reconsidered as Basis of a General Classification." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 81-95.

Bachelard, Gaston. [1940] 1968. The Philosophy of No: A Philosophy of the New Scientific Mind. New York: Orion Press.

Baldwin, James M. 1906. Thoughts and Things: A Study of the Development and Meaning of Thought, or Genetic Logic. Vol. 1: Functional Logic, or Genetic Theory of Knowledge. New York: Macmillan.

Bammé, Arno. 2011. Homo Occidentalis: Von der Anschauung zur Bemächtigung der Welt: Zäsuren abendländischer Epistemologie. Weilerswist: Velbrück.

Barnes, Michael H. 2000. Stages of Thought: The Co-Evolution of Religious Thought and Science. New York: Oxford University Press.

Bates, Marcia J. 2005. "Information and Knowledge: An Evolutionary Framework for Information Science." Information Research 10 (4). http://www.informationr.net/ir/10-4/paper239.html.

Beak, Jihee. 2014. "A Child-Driven Metadata Schema: A Holistic Analysis of Children's Cognitive Processes during Book Selection." Theses and Dissertations 449. http://dc.uwm.edu/etd/449.

Beghtol, Clare. 2000. "A Whole, Its Kinds, and Its Parts." In Dynamism and Stability in Knowledge Organization, edited by Clare Beghtol, Lynne C. Howarth, Nancy J. Williamson. Würzburg: Ergon, 313–19.

Bellah, Robert N. 2011. Religion in Human Evolution: From the Paleolithic to the Axial Age. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Bertalanffy, Ludwig von. 1968. General Systems Theory. New York: Braziller.

Blitz, David. 1992. Emergent Evolution: Qualitative Novelty and the Levels of Reality. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer.

Brier, Søren. 2003. "Information Seen as Part of the Development of Living Intelligence: The Five-Leveled Cybersemiotic Framework for FIS." Entropy 5: 88–99.

Broughton, Vanda. 2008. "Henry Evelyn Bliss: The Other Immortal, or a Prophet without Honour?" Journal of Librarianship and Information Science 40 (1): 45–58.

Broughton et al. 2005. "Knowledge Organization." In European Curriculum Reflections on Library and Information Science Education, edited by Leif Kajberg and Leif Lorring. Copenhagen: Royal School of Library and Information Science, 133–48.

Brunner-Traut, Emma. 1996. Frühformen des Erkennens: Am Beispiel Altägyptens. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.

Bunge, Mario. 2003. Emergence and Convergence: Qualitative Novelty and the Unity of Knowledge. Toronto, Buffalo, London: Toronto University Press.

Campbell, D. Grant. 2002. "Centripetal and Centrifugal Forces in Bibliographic Classification Research." Advances in Classification Research Online 13 (1): 8–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.7152/acro.v13i1.13830.

Campbell, Donald T. 1990. "Levels of Organization, Downward Causation, and the Selection-Theory Approach to Evolutionary Epistemology." In Theories of the Evolution of Knowing, edited by Gary Greenberg and Ethel Tobach. Hillsdale: Erlbaum, 1–17.

Campbell, Robert L., and Mark H. Bickhard. 1986. Knowing Levels and Developmental Stages. Basel, New York: Karger.

Cassirer, Ernst. [1923] 1955. The Philosophy of Symbolic Forms. Vol. 1: Language. New Haven: Yale University Press.

Coates, Edwards J. 1969. "CRG Proposal for a New General Classification." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 19–22.

Combs, Allan. 2009. Consiousness Explained Better: Towards an Integral Understanding of the Multifaceted Nature of Consciousness. St. Paul: Paragon.

Commons, Michael L. 2008. "Introduction to the Model of Hierarchical Complexity and Its Relationship to Postformal Action." World Futures 64: 305–20.

Commons, Michael L. et al. 1998. "Hierarchical Complexity of Tasks Shows the Existence of Developmental Stages." Developmental Review 18: 237–78.

Comte, Auguste. [1830-42] 1974. The Essential Comte: Selected from Course de Philosophie Positive, edited by Stanislav Andreski. London: Croom Helm.

Conger, George P. 1925. "The Doctrine of Levels." The Journal of Philosophy 22 (12): 309–21.

Cook-Greuter, Susanne R. [1999] 2010. Postautonomous Ego Development: A Study of Its Nature and Measurement. Tucson: Integral Publishers.

Cruse, D. Alan. 1979. "On the Transitivity of the Part-Whole Relation." Journal of Linguistics 15 (1): 29–38.

Cruse, D. Alan. 2002. "Hyponymy and Its Varieties." In The Semantics of Relations: An Interdisciplinary Perspective, edited by Rebecca Green, Carol A. Bean, and Sung Hyon Myaeng. Dordrecht: Springer, 3-21.

Dahlberg, Ingetraut. 1974. Grundlagen universaler Wissensordnung: Probleme und Möglichkeiten eines universalen Klassifikationssystems des Wissens. Pullach: Verlag Dokumentation.

Dahlberg, Ingetraut. 2008. "The Information Coding Classification: A Modern, Theory-Based Fully-Faceted, Universal System of Knowledge Fields." Axiomathes 18: 161–76.

Damerow, Peter. 1996. Abstraction and Representation: Essays on the Cultural Evolution of Thinking. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

Damerow, Peter. 1998. "Prehistory and Cognitive Development." In Piaget, Evolution, and Development, edited by Jonas Langer and Melanie Killen. Mahwah: Erlbaum, 247–70.

Damon, William, and Daniel Hart. 1988. Self-Understanding in Childhood and Adolescence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Davey, Brian A., and Hilary A. Priestley. 2008. Introduction to Lattice and Order. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

De Beer, Carel S. 2015. Information Science as an Interscience: Rethinking Science, Method and Practice. Amsterdam: Chandos Publishing.

Deacon, Terrence. 1997. The Symbolic Species: The Co-Evolution of Language and the Human Brain. London: Penguin Press.

Dilthey, Wilhelm. [1910] 2002. The Formation of the Historical World in the Human Sciences. Oxford: Princeton University Press.

Donald, Merlin. 2001. A Mind so Rare: The Evolution of Human Consciousness. New York: Norton.

Dousa, Thomas M. 2009. "Evolutionary Order in the Classification Theories of C. A. Cutter and E. C. Richardson: Its Nature and Limits." North American Symposium on Knowledge Organization 2: 76–90.

Dux, Günter. [2000] 2011. Historico-Genetic Theory of Culture: On the Processual Logic of Cultural Change. Bielefeld: Transcript.

Egan, Kieran. 1997. The Educated Mind: How Cognitive Tools Shape Our Understanding. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Elias, Norbert. [1939] 1994. The Civilizing Process: Sociogenetic and Psychogenetic Investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

Emmeche, Claus, Simo Køppe, and Frederik Stjernfelt. 1997. "Explaining Emergence: Towards an Ontology of Levels." Journal for General Philosophy of Science 28 (1): 83–117.

Erikson, Erik H. 1980. Identity and the Life Cycle. New York, London: Norton.

Esbjörn-Hargens, Sean, and Michael E. Zimmerman. 2009. Integral Ecology: Uniting Multiple Perspectives on the Natural World. Boston: Integral Books.

Farradane, Jason. 1963. "Relational Indexing and Classification in the Light of Recent Experimental Work in Psychology." Information Storage and Retrieval 1 (1): 3–11.

Feibleman, James K. 1954. "Theory of Integrative Levels." The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 5 (17): 59–66.

Feinberg, Todd E. 2011. "The Nested Neural Hierarchy and the Self." Consciousness and Cognition 20: 4–15.

Fenzl, Norbert et al. 1996. "On the Genesis of Information Structures: A View That Is Neither Reductionist nor Holistic." In Information: New Questions to a Multidisciplinary Concept, edited by Klaus Kornwachs and Konstantin Jacobi. Berlin: VCH, 271–83.

Fischer, Kurt W. 1980. "A Theory of Cognitive Development: The Control and Construction of Hierarchies of Skills." Psychological Review 87: 477–531.

Forsche, Joachim B. 1965. Zur Philosophie Nicolai Hartmanns: Die Problematik von kategorialer Schichtung und Realdetermination. Meisenheim am Glan: Hain.

Foskett, Douglas J. 1961. "Classification and Integrative Levels." In The Sayers Memorial Volume: Essays in Librarianship in Memory of William Charles Berwick Sayers, edited by Douglas J. Foskett and Bernard I. Palmer, 136–50.

Foskett, Douglas J. 1962. "The Classification Research Group 1952-1962." International Journal of Libraries and Informarion Services 12 (2): 127–38.

Foskett, Douglas J. 1978. "The Theory of Integrative Levels and Its Relevance to the Design of Information Systems." ASLIB Proceedings 30 (6): 202–8.

Foskett, Douglas J. 1980. "Systems Theory and Its Relevance to Documentary Classification." International Classification 7 (1): 2–5.

Fowler, James W. 1981. Stages of Faith: The Psychology of Human Development and the Quest for Meaning. San Francisco: Harper & Row.

Frické, Martin. 2016. "Logical Division." Knowledge Organization 43 (7): 539–49.

Gablik, Suzi. 1979. Progress in Art. New York: Rizzoli.

García Gutiérrez, Antonio. 2011. "Declassification in Knowledge Organization: A Post-Epistemological Essay." Transinformaçao 23 (1): 5–14.

Gebser, Jean. [1949] 1985. The Ever-Present Origin. Athens: Ohio University Press.

Gnoli, Claudio. 2005. "BC2 Classes for Phenomena: An Application of the Theory of Integrative Levels." The Bliss Classification Bulletin 47: 17–21.

Gnoli, Claudio. 2008. "Categories and Facets in Integrative Levels." Axiomathes 18: 177–92.

Gnoli, Claudio. 2015. "The Value Added of Organized Information: From Floridi to Bennett." In Knowledge Organization: Making a Difference. Proceedings ISKO Biennial Conference, London, July 2015, edited by Stella Dextre Clarke. http://www.iskouk.org/sites/default/files/Gnoli-PaperISKO-UK2015.pdf.

Gnoli, Claudio. 2017. "Classifying Phenomena. Part 2: Types and Levels." Knowledge Organization 44 (1): 37–54.

Gnoli, Claudio, Mela Bosch, and Fulvio Mazzocchi. 2007. "A New Relation for Multidisciplinary Knowledge Organization Systems: Dependence." In Interdisciplinarity and Transdisciplinarity in the Organization of Scientific Knowledge. Proceedings of the 8th ISKO-Spain Conference 18-20 April 2007 León, Spain, edited by Blanca Rodríguez Bravo and Dietz, Maria L. A. Dietz. León: Universidad de León, 399-409.

Gnoli, Claudio, Rodrigo De Santis, and Laura Pusterla. 2015. "Commerce, See Also Rhetoric: Cross-Discipline Relationships as Authority Data for Enhanced Retrieval." In Classification & Authority Control: Expanding Resource Discovery, edited by Aida Slavic and Maria I. Cordeiro. Würzburg: Ergon, 151-62.

Gnoli, Claudio, and Roberto Poli. 2004. "Levels of Reality and Levels of Representation." Knowledge Organization 31 (3): 151–60.

Gnoli, Claudio, and Riccardo Ridi. 2014. "Unified Theory of Information, Hypertextuality and Levels of Reality." Journal of Documentation 70 (3): 443–60.

Graves, Clare W. 1970. "Levels of Existence: An Open System Theory of Values." Journal of Humanistic Psychology 10 (2): 131–55.

Greenberg, Gary. 1995. "Anagenetic Theory in Comparative Psychology." International Journal of Comparative Psychology 8 (1): 31–41.

Greenberg, Gary, and G. Y. Kenyon. 1987. "Issues for Continuing Discussion of Integrative Levels." In Cognition, Language and Consciousness: Integrative Levels, edited by Gary Greenberg and Ethel Tobach. Hillsdale: Erlbaum, 277–88.

Greenberg, Gary, et al. 1999. "Integrative Levels, the Brain, and the Emergence of Complex Behavior." Review of General Psychology 3 (3): 168–87.

Guizzardi, Giancarlo. 2009. "The Problem of Transitivity of Part-Whole Relations in Conceptual Modeling Revisited." In Advanced Information Systems Engineering: 21st International Conference CAiSE 2009, edited by Pascal van Eck, Jaap Gordijn, and Roel Wieringa. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer, 94–109.

Haaften, Wouter van, Michiel Korthals, and Thomas Wren, eds. 1997. Philosophy of Development: Reconstructing the Foundations of Human Development and Education. Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1979. Communication and the Evolution of Society. Boston: Beacon.

Habermas, Jürgen. 1990. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge: MIT Press.

Hallpike, Christopher R. 2008. How We Got Here: From Bows and Arrows to the Space Age. Milton Keynes: AuthorHouse.

Hartmann, Nicolai. 1940. Der Aufbau der realen Welt: Grundriß der Allgemeinen Kategorienlehre. Berlin: De Gruyter.

Hartmann, Nicolai. [1942] 1953. New Ways of Ontology. Chicago: Regnery.

Hegel, Georg W. F. [1830] 1970. Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Vol. 2: Philosophy of Nature. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

Herder, Johann G. 1800. Outlines of a Philosophy of the History of Man. London: Johnson.

Herre, Heinrich. 2013. "Formal Ontology and the Foundation of Knowledge Organization." Knowledge Organization 40 (5): 332–33.

Hjørland, Birger. 2002. "Principia Informatica: Foundational Theory of Information and Principles of Information Services." In Emerging Frameworks and Methods. Proceedings of the Fourth International Conference on Conceptions of Library and Information Science (CoLIS4), edited by Harry Bruce, Raya Fidel, Peter Ingwersen, and Pertti Vakkari. Greenwood Village: Libraries Unlimited, 109–21.

Hjørland, Birger. 2017. "Classification." ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization. https://www.isko.org/cyclo/classification.

Hobhouse, Leonard T. 1901. Mind in Evolution. London: Macmillan.

Huckaby, Sarah A. S. 1972. "An Enquiry into the Theory of Integrative Levels as the Basis for a Generalized Classification Scheme." Journal of Documentation 28 (2): 97–106.

ISKO Italy. 2007. "The León Manifesto." Knowledge Organization 34 (1): 6–8.

Jacob, Elin K. 2000. "The Legacy of Pragmatism: Implications for Knowledge Organization in a Pluralistic Universe." In Dynamism and Stability in Knowledge Organization. Proceedings of the 6th International ISKO Conference, 10-13 July 2000 Toronto, Canada, edited by Clare Beghtol, Lynne C. Howarth, and Nancy J. Williamson. Würzburg: Ergon, 16–22.

Jacob, Elin K. 2004. "Classification and Categorization: A Difference That Makes a Difference." Library Trends 52 (3): 515–40.

Jantsch, Erich. [1979] 1980. The Self-Organizing Universe: Scientific and Human Implications of the Emerging Paradigm of Evolution. Oxford, New York: Pergamon Press.

Jolley, John L. 1973. The Fabric of Knowledge: A Study of the Relations between Ideas. London: Duckworth.

Kegan, Robert. 1982. The Evolving Self: Problem and Process in Human Development. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Kegan, Robert. 1994. In over Our Heads: The Mental Demands of Modern Life. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.

King, Patricia M., and Karen S. Kitchener. 1994. Developing Reflective Judgment: Understanding and Promoting Intellectual Growth and Critical Thinking in Adolescents and Adults. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass.

Kleineberg, Michael. 2013. "The Blind Men and the Elephant: Towards an Organization of Epistemic Contexts." Knowledge Organization 40 (5): 340–62.

Kleineberg, Michael. 2014. "Integrative Levels of Knowing: An Organizing Principle for the Epistemological Dimension." In Knowledge Organization in the 21st Century: Between Historical Patterns and Future Prospects. Proceedings of the 13th International ISKO Conference 2014, edited by Wieslaw Babik. Würzburg: Ergon, 80–87.

Kleineberg, Michael. 2016. "From Linearity to Co-Evolution: On the Architecture of Nicolai Hartmann's Levels of Reality." In New Research on the Philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann, edited by Keith Peterson and Roberto Poli. Berlin, Boston: De Gruyter, 81–108.

Koestler, Arthur. 1967. The Ghost in the Machine. London: Arkana.

Kohlberg, Lawrence, and Richard H. Hersh. 1977. "Moral Development: A Review of the Theory." Theory Into Practice 16 (2): 53–59.

Kramer, Deidre A. 1989. "Development of an Awareness of Contradiction across the Life Span and the Question of Postformal Operations." In Adult Development. Vol. 1: Comparisons and Applications of Developmental Models, edited by Michael Commons, Jan D. Sinnott, Fracis A. Richards, and Cheryl Armon. Westport, London: Praeger, 133–59.

Kuhn, Thomas S. 2000. The Road since Structure: Philosophical Essays, 1970-1993, with an Autobiographical Interview. Chicago, London: University of Chicago Press.

Kummer, Christian. 1987. Evolution als Höherentwicklung des Bewußtseins. Freiburg, München: Alber.

Kyle, Barbara R.F. 1969. "Lessons Learned from Experiences in Drafting the Kyle Classification." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 11–16.

Lamarck, Jean-Baptiste. [1809] 1914. Zoological Philosophy: An Exposition with Regard to the Natural History of Animals. London: Macmillan.

Langridge, Derek W. 1976. Classification and Indexing in the Humanities. London: Butterworths.

Leibniz, Gottfried W. 2014. Leibniz's Monadology: A New Translation and Guide. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

Leontiev, Alexei N. [1977] 2009. "Activity, Consciousness, and Personality." In Activity and Consciousness. Pacifica: Marxist Internet Archive, 27–192.

LePan, Don. 1989. The Cognitive Revolution in Western Culture: The Birth of Expectation. Houndsmill, London: Macmillan.

Linnaeus, Carl. 1758. Systema Naturae: Per Regna Tria Naturae Secundum Classes, Ordines, Genera, Species, Vol. 1. Stockholm: Laurentii Salvi.

Lobo, Ingrid. 2008. "Biological Complexity and Integrative Levels of Organization." Nature Education 1 (1): 141.

Loevinger, Jane. 1998. "Reliability and Validity of SCT." In Technical Foundations for Measuring Ego Development: The Washington University Sentence Completion Test, edited by Jane Loevinger. Mahwah: Erlbaum, 33–43.

López-Huertas, María J. 2013. "Reflexions on Multidimensional Knowledge: Its Influence on the Foundation of Knowledge Organization." Knowledge Organization 40 (6): 400–407.

Lorenz, Konrad. 1977. Behind the Mirror: A Search for a Natural History of Human Knowledge. New York, London: Harvest.

Lourenço, Orlando M. 2016. "Developmental Stages, Piagetian Stages in Particular: A Critical Review." New Ideas in Psychology 40: 123–37.

Lovejoy, Arthur O. 1936. The Great Chain of Being: A Study of the History of an Idea. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.

Luria, Alexander R. 1976. The Cognitive Development: Its Cultural and Social Foundations. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Mai, Jens-Erik. 2011. "The Modernity of Classification." Journal of Documentation 67 (4): 710–30.

Mannheim, Karl. 1982. Structures of Thinking. Collected Works of Karl Mannheim, Vol. 10. London: Routledge.

Maslow, Abraham H. 1943. "A Theory of Human Motivation." Psychological Review 50: 370–96.

Mithen, Steven. 1996. The Prehistory of the Mind: A Search for the Origins of Art, Religion and Science. London: Phoenix.

Morgan, C. Lloyd. 1923. Emergent Evolution. The Gifford Lectures. London: Williams and Norgate.

Mortimer, Eduardo F. et al. 2014. "Conceptual Profiles: Theoretical-Methodological Bases of a Research Program." In Conceptual Profiles: A Theory of Teaching and Learning Scientific Concepts, edited by Eduardo F. Mortimer and Charbel N. El-Hani. Dordrecht: Springer, 3–33.

Needham, Joseph. 1937. Integrative Levels: A Revaluation of the Idea of Progress. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Neumann, Erich. [1949] 1975. The Origins and History of Consciousness. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Nicolescu, Basarab. 2010. "Methodology of Transdisciplinarity: Levels of Reality, Logic of the Included Middle and Complexity." Transdisciplinary Journal of Engineering and Science 1 (1): 19–38.

Nolan, Patrick, and Gerhard Lenski. 2015. Human Societies. An Introduction to Macrosociology. New York: Oxford University Press.

Novikoff, Alex B. 1945. "The Concept of Integrative Levels and Biology." Science 101 (2618): 209–15.

Oesterdiekhoff, Georg W. 2013. "Relevance of Piagetian Cross-Cultural Psychology to the Humanities and Social Sciences." The American Journal of Psychology 126 (4): 477–92.

Olson, Hope A. 1999. "Exclusivity, Teleology and Hierarchy: Our Aristotelean Legacy." Knowledge Organization 26 (2): 65–73.

Oppenheimer, Paul, and Hilary Putnam. 1958. "Unity of Science as a Working Hypothesis." In Concepts, Theories, and the Mind-Body Problem, edited by Herbert Feigl, Michael Scriven, and Grover Maxwell. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 3–36.

Overton, Willis F. 2006. "Developmental Psychology: Philosophy, Concepts, Methodology." In Handbook of Child Psychology. Vol. 1: Theoretical Models of Human Development, edited by Richard M. Lerner and William Damon.Hoboken: Wiley, 18–88.

Parker, Sue T., and Anne E. Russon. 1996. "On the Wild Side of Culture and Cognition in the Great Apes." In Reaching into Thought: The Minds of the Great Apes, edited by Anne E. Russon, Kim A. Bard, and Sue T. Parker. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 430–50.

Parsons, Michael J. 1987. How We Understand Art: A Cognitive Developmental Account of Aesthetic Experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Perry, William G. 1968. Forms of Intellectual and Ethical Development in the College Years: A Scheme. New York: Holt, Rinehart & Winston.

Pettersson, Max. 1996. Complexity and Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Piaget, Jean. 1977. The Essential Piaget: An Interpretive Reference and Guide. Edited by Howard E. Gruber and J. Jacques Vonèche. New York: Basic Books.

Pisula, Wojciech. 2009. Curiosity and Information Seeking in Animal and Human Behavior. Boca Raton: Brown Walker Press.

Pisula, Wojciech. 2016. "Levels of Consciousness." Open Journal of Philosophy 6 (1): 51–58.

Plato. 1929. "Timaeus." In Timeaus. Critias. Cleitophon. Menexenus. Epistles, 1–253. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Plato. 2013. Republic. Vol. 1-2. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

Plotinus. 1992. Enneads. Burdett: Larson.

Poli, Roberto. 2001. "The Basic Problem of the Theory of Levels of Reality." Axiomathes 12: 261–83.

Priss, Uta. 2004. "Multilevel Approaches to Concepts and Formal Ontologies." In Advances in classification research. Vol. 12: Proceedings of the 12th ASIST SIG/CR Classification Research Workshop held at the 64th ASIST Annual Meeting, November 2-8, 2001, edited by Efthimis N. Efthimiadis. Washington, D.C. Medford: Information Today, 53–66.

Pseudo-Dionysius the Aeropagite. 1987. "The Celestial Hierarchy." In Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works, edited by John Farina. Mahwah: Paulist, 143–91.

Quilley, Stephen. 2010. "Integrative Levels and 'the Great Evolution': Organicist Biology and the Sociology of Norbert Elias." Journal of Classical Sociology 10 (4): 391–419.

Rajasurya et al. 2012. "Semantic Information Retrieval Using Ontology in University Domain." International Journal of Web and Semantic Technology 3 (4): 55–68.

Ranganathan, Shiyali R. 1937. Prolegomena to Library Classification. 3rd ed. London: Asia Publihsing House.

Reiser, Oliver L. 1958. The Integration of Human Knowledge: A Study of the Formal Foundations and the Social Implications of Unified Science. Boston: Porter Sargent.

Richardson, Ernest C. 1901. Classification: Theoretical and Practical. New York: Scribner.

Richmond, Phyllis A. 1965. "Contribution toward a New Generalized Theory of Classification." In Proceedings of the 2nd International Study Conference on Classification Research, edited by Pauline Atherton. Copenhagen: Munksgaard, 39–54.

Robinson, Lyn, and Mike Maguire. 2010. "The Rhizome and the Tree: Changing Metaphors for Information Organisation." Journal of Documentation 66 (4): 604–13.

Roetz, Heiner. 1993. Confucian Ethics of the Axial Age: A Reconstruction under the Aspect of the Breakthrough towards Postconventional Thinking. New York: State University of New York Press.

Rowe, J. Stan. 1961. "The Level-of-integration Concept and Ecology." Ecology 42 (2): 420–27.

Sahlins, Marshall D., and Elman R. Service. [1960] 1988. Evolution and Culture. Ann Arbor: The University of Michigan Press.

Salthe, Stanley N. 1991. "Two Forms of Hierarchy Theory in Western Discourses." International Journal of General Systems 18 (3): 251–64.

Salthe, Stanley N. 2009. "A Hierarchical Framework for Levels of Reality: Understanding through Representation." Axiomathes 19 (1): 87–99.

Šamurin, Evgenij I. [1955] 1977. Geschichte der bibliothekarisch-bibliographischen Klassifikation. Vol. 1-2. Munich: Verlag Dokumentation.

Santis, Rodrigo De, and Claudio Gnoli. 2016. "Expressing Dependence Relationships in the Integrative Levels Classification Using OWL." In Knowledge Organization for a Sustainable World: Challenges and Perspectives for Cultural, Scientific, and Technological Sharing in a Connected Society, edited by José Augusto Guimaraes, Suellen Oliveira Milani and Vera Dodebei. Würzburg: Ergon, 368–75.

Scheler, Max. [1924] 1980. Problems of a Sociology of Knowledge. Routledge.

Schelling, Friedrich W. J. [1800] 1978. System of Transcendental Idealism. Charlottesville: University Press of Virgina.

Schluchter, Wolfgang. [1979] 1981. The Rise of Western Rationalism: Max Weber's Developmental History. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of California Press.

Scrivner, Buford. 1980. "Carolingian Monastic Library Catalogs and Medieval Classification of Knowledge." The Journal of Library History 15 (4): 427–44.

Selman, Robert L. 1980. The Growth of Interpersonal Understanding: Developmental and Clinical Analyses. New York, London, Toronto, Sydney, San Francisco: Academic Press.

Smith, Huston. [1976] 1992. Forgotten Truth: The Common Vision of the World's Religions. New York: Harper One.

Spencer, Herbert. [1862] 1915. A System of Synthetic Philosophy, Vol. 1: First Principles. London: Williams & Norgate.

Spencer, Herbert. 1873. A System of Synthetic Philosophy, Vol. 4: The Principles of Psychology, Vol. 1. New York: Appleton.

Spencer, Herbert. 1883. A System of Synthetic Philosophy, Vol. 6: The Principles of Sociology. New York: Appleton.

Spiteri, Louise F. 1995. "The Classification Research Group and the Theory of Integrative Levels." Katharine Sharp Review 1: 1–6.

Stern, Daniel N. [1985] 2006. The Interpersonal World of the Infant: A View from Psychoanalysis and Developmental Psychology. London, New York: Karnac.

Steward, Julian H. 1972. Theory of Cultural Change: The Methodology of Multininear Evolution. Urbana, Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

Stock, Wolfgang, and Mechthild Stock. 2013. Handbook of Information Science. Berlin: De Gruyter.

Svenonius, Elaine. 2000. The Intellectual Foundation of Information Organization. Cambridge, London: MIT Press.

Svenonius, Elaine. 2004. "The Epistemological Foundation of Knowledge Representation." Library Trends 52 (3): 571–87.

Szostak, Rick. 2012. "The Basic Concepts Classification." In Categories, contexts and relations in knowledge organization. Proceedings of the 12th International ISKO Conference 6-9 August 2012 Mysore, India, edited by Arashanipalai Neelameghan, Koti S. Raghavan. Würzburg: Ergon, 24–30.

Szostak, Rick, Claudio Gnoli, and Mari´a J. Lo´pez-Huertas. 2016. Interdisciplinary Knowledge Organization. Cham: Springer.

Teilhard de Chardin, Pierre. [1955] 1959. The Phenomenon of Man. New York: Harper.

Thompson, William I. 1996. Coming into Being: Artifacts and Texts in the Evolution of Consciousness. New York: St. Martins Press.

Tobach, Ethel. 1987. "Integrative Levels in the Comparative Psychology of Cognition, Language, and Consciousness." In Cognition, Language, and Consciousness: Integrative Levels. The T.C. Schneirla Conference Series, Vol. 2, edited by Garry Greenberg and Ethel Tobach. Hillsdale, London: Erlbaum, 239–67.

Tolman, Charles W. 1987. "Human Evolution and the Comparative Psychology of Levels." In Cognition, Language, and Consciousness: Integrative Levels. The T.C. Schneirla Conference Series, Vol. 2, edited by Garry Greenberg and Ethel Tobach. Hillsdale, London: Erlbaum, 185–207.

Tomasello, Michael. 2014. A Natural History of Human Thinking. Cambridge, London: Harvard University Press.

Tomlinson, Helen. 1969a. "Problems Arising from First CRG Papers." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 73–80.

Tomlinson, Helen. 1969b. "Report on Work for New General Classification Scheme." In Classification and Information Control: Papers Representing the Work of the Classification Research Group during 1960-1968, edited by Classification Research Group. London: The Library Association, 29–41.

Torbert, Bill et al. 2004. Action Inquiry: The Secret of Timely and Transforming Leadership. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler.

Trigger, Bruce G. 2003. Understanding Early Civilizations: A Comparative Study. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Turiel, Elliot. 1983. The Development of Social Knowledge: Morality and Convention. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Vickery, Brian C. 1958. Classification and Indexing in Science. London: Butterworth.

Vickery, Brian C. 2005. "The Material Mind." In Brian Vickery at home. http://iva.dk/bh/Core%20Concepts%20in%20LIS/articles%20a-z/Vickery_texts.htm.

Vroman, Leo. 1995. "Definitions of Levels of Integration." In Behavioral Development: Concepts of Approach/withdrawal and Integrative Levels, edited by Kathryn E. Hood, Gary Greenberg, and Ethel Tobach. New York, London: Garland, 417–20.

Vygotsky, Lev S. [1934] 1986. Thought and Language. Massachusetts: MIT Press.

Wear, Sarah K., and John M. Dillon. 2007. Dionysius the Areopagite and the Neoplatonist Tradition: Despoiling the Hellenes. Adlershot: Ashgate.

Werner, Heinz, and Bernhard Kaplan. 1956. "The Developmental Approach to Cognition: Its Relevance to the Psychological Interpretation of Anthropological and Ethnolinguistic Data." American Anthropologist 58: 866–80.

Wheeler, William M. 1928. Emergent Evolution and the Development of Societies. New York: Norton.

Whitehead, Alfred N. [1929] 1978. Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology. New York: The Free Press.

Wilber, Ken. 1993. "The Great Chain of Being." Journal of Humanistic Psychology 33 (3): 52–65.

Wilber, Ken. [1995] 2000. "Sex, Ecology, Spirituality: The Spirit of Evolution." In The Collected Works of Ken Wilber, Vol. 6, 2nd ed. Boston, London: Shambhala, 1–825.

Wilber, Ken. 1999. "Integral Psychology: Consciousness, Spirit, Psychology, Therapy." In The Collected Works of Ken Wilber, Vol. 4. Boston, London: Shambhala, 423–717.

Wilson, Thomas D. 2003. "Philosophical Foundations and Research Relevance: Issues for Information Research." Journal of Information Science 29 (6): 445–52.

Winston, Morton, Roger Chaffin, and Douglas Herrmann. 1987. "A Taxonomy of Part-Whole Relations." Cognitive Science 11: 417–44.

Wundt, Wilhelm. [1912] 1916. Elements of Folk Psychology: Outlines of Psychological History of the Development of Mankind. New York: Macmillan.

Wynn, Thomas. 1985. "Piaget, Stone Tools and the Evolution of Human Intelligence." World Archaeology 17 (1): 32–43.

Yao, Yiyu. 2009. "Integrative Levels of Granularity." In Human-Centric Information Processing through Granular Modelling, edited by Andrzej Bargiela and Witold Pedrycz. Berlin, Heidelberg: Springer, 31–47.

[top of entry]

Appendix A: Sample of sequences based on the idea of integrative levels

(Excerpts are in chronological order of original publication. Numbering is added, M.K.)


Comte, Auguste ([1830-42] 1974, 55):

Phenomena

1. Physical
2. Chemical
3. Physiological
4. Social


Comte, Auguste ([1830-42] 1974, 20):

Human mind

1. Theological or fictitious
2. Metaphysical or abstract
3. Scientific or positive


Spencer, Herbert (1883, 3):

Phenomena

1. Inorganic
2. Organic
3. Super-organic


Hobhouse, Leonard T. (1901, 359–68):

Human mind

1. Pre-intelligence
2. Unconscious readjustment
3. Concrete experience and the practical judgment
4. Conceptual thinking and will
5. Rational system


Richardson, Ernest C. (1901, 30):

Things

1. Lifeless
2. Living
3. Human
4. Superhuman


Baldwin, James M. (1906, 33):

Cognition

1. Pre-logical
2. Quasi-logical
3. Logical
4. Hyper-logical
5. Extra-logical


Alexander, Samuel ([1920] 1950, Vol. II: 52, 345):

Entities

1. Space-time
2. Matter
3. Life
4. Mind
5. Deity


Morgan, Conwy Lloyd (1923, 27):

Events

1. Matter (with psychical correlates)
2. Life (with psychical correlates)
3. Mind (with physical correlates)


Conger, George P. (1925, 312–113):

Material realm

1. Energies
2. Electrons
3. Atoms
4. Molecules
5. Astronomical masses, or bodies
6. Solar systems
7. Star clusters
8. Galaxies
9. Universes


Conger, George P. (1925, 313):

Biological realm

1. Organic compounds
2. Infra-cellular organisms
3. Unicellular organisms
4. Multicellular organisms
5. Plant-and-animal groups
6. Families or tribes
7. Nations
8. "The Great Society"


Conger, George P. (1925, 313):

Neuropsychological realm

1. Specialized cells
2. Nervous areas
3. Reflex arcs
4. Complex reflexes
5. Instinctive emotional complexes
6. Sentiments
7. Values
8. Personalities


Wheeler, William M. (1928, 74):

Phenomena

1. Physical
2. Chemical
3. Psychological
4. Social


Vygotsky, Lev S. ([1934] 1986, 140):

Concept formation

1. Syncretic
2. Complex (pseudoconcept)
3. Potential concept
4. True concept


Needham, Joseph (1937, 6):

Phenomena

1. Inorganic
2. Biological
3. Social


Bachelard, Gaston ([1940] 1968, 15):

Philosophical explanation

1. Animism
2. Realism
3. Positivism
4. Rationalism
5. Complex rationalism
6. Dialectical rationalism


Hartmann, Nicolai (1940, 498):

Nature

1. Matter
2. Life


Hartmann, Nicolai ([1942] 1953, 46):

Consciousness

1. Spiritless (psyche)
2. Spiritual (personal spirit)


Novikoff, Alex B. (1945, 209):

Matter

1. Physical
2. Chemical
3. Biological
4. Sociological


Novikoff, Alex B. (1945, 211):

Biological matter

1. Cells
2. Tissues
3. Organs
4. Organ-systems
5. Organisms
6. Populations


Gebser, Jean ([1949] 1985, 42):

Consciousness

1. Archaic
2. Magical
3. Mythical
4. Mental
5. Integral


Neumann, Erich ([1949] 1975, 264):

Collective consciousness (mythology)

1. Uroboros
2. Great Mother
3. Dragon fight


Piaget, Jean ([1952] 1977, 456–61):

Cognition

1. Sensorimotor
2. Preoperational
3. Concrete operational
4. Formal operational


Feibleman, James K. (1954, 60–62):

Organizations

1. Electrons, protons, neutrons
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Cells
5. Organisms
6. Human cultures


Feibleman, James K. (1954, 63):

Properties (behavior)

1. Physical (cause-and-effect)
2. Chemical (combination-rearrangement)
3. Biological (sensitivity-reactivity)
4. Psychological (stimulus-response)
5. Cultural (contact-adaptation)


Steward, Julian H. ([1955] 1972, 190):

Societies

1. Hunting and gathering
2. Incipient agriculture
3. Formative
4. Regional florescent
5. Initial empire


Oppenheim, Paul and Putnam, Hilary (1958, 9):

Things

1. Elementary particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Cells
5. Multicellular living things
6. Social groups


Sahlin, Marshall D. and Service, Elman R. ([1960] 1988, 37):

Social systems

1. Unsegmented and chiefless bands (preagricultural)
2. Segmented and chiefless tribes (agricultural)
3. Segmented chiefdoms
4. Archaic civilizations
5. Nation states (industrial technology)


Rowe, J. Stan (1961, 422):

Objects

1. Cell
2. Organ
3. Organism
4. Ecosystem (single organism-habitat)
5. Local Ecosystem
6. Regional Ecosystem
7. Ecosphere
8. Universe


Forsche, Joachim (1965, 124; my translation, M.K.):

Material structures

1. Elementary particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Polymeres
5. Macromolecules
6. Viruses
7. Cells
8. Organisms
9. Organisms with central nervous system
10. Specific human structure


Richmond, Phyllis (1965, 43):

Mentefacts

1. An observation
2. A group of observations
3. 1st level generalization
4. 2nd level generalization
5. A law


Bertalanffy, Ludwig von (1968, 27):

Organized entities

1. Elementary particles
2. Atomic nuclei
3. Atoms
4. Molecules
5. High-molecular compounds
6. Structures between molecules and cells
7. Cells
8. Organisms
9. Supra-individual organizations


Bertalanffy, Ludwig von (1968, 87):

Systems

1. Physical
2. Chemical
3. Biological
4. Sociological


Bertalanffy, Ludwig von (1968, 214):

Mental systems

1. Instincts, drives, emotions
2. Perception, voluntary action
3. Symbolic activities


Perry, William G. (1968, folded chart):

Intelligence and ethics

1. Simple dualism
2. Complex dualism
3. Relativism
4. Commitment in relativism


Austin, Derek (1969c, 88):

Entities

1. Fundamental particles
2. Elements
3. Compounds
4. Living Compounds


Kyle, Barbara (1969, 14):

Entities

1. Inorganic
2. Vegetable
3. Animal
4. Man
5. Groups
6. Formal groups
7. Government local
8. Government central
9. Intergovernmental


Coates, Edwards J. (1969, 21):

Organized wholes

1. Fundamental particles
2. Nuclei
3. Atoms
4. Molecules
5. Molecular assemblages (natural objects and artifacts)
6. Cells
7. Organisms
8. Human beings
9. Human societies


Tomlinson, Helen (1969b, 30):

Physical entities

1. Fundamental particle
2. Atom
3. Molecule
4. Molecule assemblage
5. Physical structure
6. Physiographic feature
7. Planet
8. Collection of Planets
9. Universe


Tomlinson, Helen (1969b, 30):

Chemical entities

1. Element
2. Radical
3. Compound
4. Complex
5. Aggregate


Tomlinson, Helen (1969b, 30):

Artefacts

1. Raw material
2. Worked substance
3. Compound
4. Assemblage of compounds
5. Finished complex article


Tomlinson, Helen (1969b, 30):

Biological entities

1. Crystal complex
2. Organelle
3. Cell
4. Tissue
5. Organ
6. Organ system
7. Whole organism
8. Community


Tomlinson, Helen (1969b, 33):

Man

1. Individual
2. Families
3. Urban communities
4. Groups of towns
5. States
6. Intergovernmental units


Tomlinson, Helen (1969a, 79):

Mentefacts

1. Word
2. Sentence
3. Paragraph
4. Complete work


Jolley, John L. (1973, 30):

Ideas

1. Set-theoretic (e.g., members of sets, full sets)
2. Spatial (e.g., points, lines and linear spaces)
3. Subatomic (e.g., photons, electrons)
4. Molecular (e.g., atoms, molecules)
5. Cytomechanic (e.g., organelles, cells)
6. Biomorphic (e.g., organs, plants and animals, machines)
7. Communal (e.g., departments, organizations)
8. National (e.g., local goverments, nations)


Smith, Huston ([1976] 1992, 62):

Selfhood (traditional Great Chain of Being)

1. Body
2. Mind
3. Soul
4. Spirit


Kohlberg, Lawrence and Hersh, Richard H. (1977, 54–55):

Moral judgment

1. Punishment-and-obedience (preconventional)
2. Instrumental-relativist
3. Interpersonal concordance (conventional)
4. Law and order
5. Social-contract, legalistic (postconventional)
6. Universal-ethical-principle


Apel, Karl-Otto (1978, 9):

Paradigms of First Philosophy

1. General metaphysics (ontology)
2. Transcendental philosophy (consciousness)
3. Transcendental semiotics (language)


Habermas, Jürgen (1979, 83):

Communicative action

1. Incomplete interaction (natural identity, consequences of actions)
2. Complete interaction (role identity, systems of norms)
3. Communicative action and discourse (ego identity, principles)


Habermas, Jürgen (1979, 100–101):

Ego identity

1. Symbiotic
2. Egocentric
3. Sociocentric-objectivistic
4. Universalistic


Habermas, Jürgen (1979, 104–5):

Worldview

1. Magical-animistic
2. Early mythological
3. Late mythological
4. Rationalized
5. Reflexive


Habermas, Jürgen (1979, 157–58):

Social integration

1. Neolithic societies
2. Early civilizations
3. Developed civilizations
4. The modern age


Jantsch, Erich ([1979] 1980, 132):

Self-organizing microsystems

1. Dissipative structures
2. Prokaryotes
3. Eukaryotes
4. Multicellular organisms
5. Complex animals


Jantsch, Erich ([1979] 1980, 132):

Self-organizing macrosystems

1. Planetary chemodynamics
2. Gaia system
3. Heterotrophic ecosystems
4. Societies with division of labor
5. Groups, families


Jantsch, Erich ([1979] 1980, 240):

Self-organizing mind (mentation)

1. Dissipative structures (intracellular processes)
2. Organelles (prokaryotes)
3. Cells (eukaryotes)
4. Organism/organismic mentation
5. Reflexive mentation (gestalt perception)
6. Self-reflexive mentation (sociocultural dimension)
7. Self-image


Schluchter, Wolfgang ([1979] 1981, 102):

Ethics and law

1. Magic ethics and revealed law
2. Law ethics and traditional law
3. Ethics of conviction and deduced law
4. Ethics of responsibility and positive law


Fischer, Kurt (1980, 522):

Skills

1. Single sensory-motor sets
2. Sensory-motor mappings
3. Sensory-motor systems
4. System of sensory-motor systems (single representational sets)
5. Representational mappings
6. Representational systems
7. Systems of representational systems (single abstract sets)
8. Abstract mappings
9. Abstract systems
10. Systems of abstract systems


Selman, Robert L. (1980, 37–40):

Interpersonal understanding

1. Undifferentiated, egocentric
2. Differentiated, subjective
3. Self-reflective, second-person, reciprocal
4. Third-person, mutual
5. In-depth, societal-symbolic


Fowler, James W. (1981, 113):

Faith

1. Undifferentiated
2. Intuitive-projective
3. Mythic-literal
4. Synthetic-conventional
5. Individualistic-reflective
6. Conjunctive
7. Universalizing


Leontiev, Alexei N. ([1981] quoted in Tolman 1987, 199):

Activity

1. Irritability
2. Sensitivity
3. Perceptivity
4. Animal intellect
5. Human consciousness


Turiel, Elliot (1983, 106–11):

Social-conventional concepts

1. Descriptive of uniformity
2. Related to rule and authority system
3. Mediated by societal standards
4. Functional


Stern, Daniel N. ([1985] 2006, 32):

Sense of self

1. Emergent
2. Core
3. Subjective
4. Verbal


Parsons, Michel J. (1987, 22–25):

Aesthetic experience

1. Favoritism
2. Beauty and realism
3. Expressiveness
4. Style and form
5. Autonomy


Damon, William and Hart, Daniel (1988, 56):

Self-understanding

1. Categorical identifications
2. Comparative assessments
3. Inter-personal implications
4. Systematic beliefs and plans


Kramer, Deidre A. (1989, 153):

Social cognition

1. Undifferentiation
2. Pre-formism
3. Formism, mechanism
4. Static relativism
5. Static systems
6. Dynamic relativism
7. Dynamic dialecticism


Atran, Scott (1990, 79):

Human cognition

1. First-order concepts (common-sense)
2. Second-order concepts (science)


Campbell, Donald T. (1990, 11):

Knowledge processes

1. Nonmnemonic problem solving
2. Vicarious locomotor devices (distance receptors)
3. Habit
4. Instinct
5. Visually supported thought
6. Mnemonically supported thought (including computer problem solving)
7. Social vicarious exploration
8. Language
9. Cultural cumulation
10. Science


Blitz, David (1992, 181):

Material or physical-chemical entities

1. Subatomic particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Macromolecules


Blitz, David (1992, 181–82):

Biological or cellular-organismic entities

1. Cell-components
2. Prokaryotic cells
3. Eukaryotic cells
4. Multi-celled organisms (e.g., fungi, plants animals)


Blitz, David (1992, 182):

Social or populational entities

1. Social insects (fixed)
2. Higher primates (greater variability)
3. Humans (greatest variability)


Blitz, David (1992, 182):

Mental or perceptual-conceptual entities

1. Sensation
2. Perception
3. Cognition
4. Intelligence
5. Consciousness


Blitz, David (1992, 183):

Entities

1. Matter
2. Life
3. Society
4. Mind


Wilber, Ken (1993, 53):

Being and knowing (traditional Great Chain of Being)

1. Matter
2. Body
3. Mind
4. Soul
5. Spirit


Kegan, Robert (1994, 314–15):

Consciousness

1. Immediate, atomistic
2. Durable category
3. Cross-categorical, trans-categorical (e.g., traditionalism)
4. System, complex (e.g., modernism)
5. Trans-system, trans-complex (e.g., post-modernism)


King, Patricia M. and Kitchener, Karen S. (1994, 14–15):

Reflective judgment

1. Pre-reflective
2. Quasi-reflective
3. Reflective


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 15):

Phenomena

1. Physiosphere
2. Biosphere
3. Noosphere


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 198):

Exterior-individual holons (behavioral)

1. Atoms
2. Molecules
3. Prokaryotes
4. Eukaryotes
5. Neural organisms
6. Neural cord organisms
7. Reptilian brain stem organisms
8. Limbic system organisms
9. Neo-cortex organisms
10. Complex neo-cortex organisms


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 198):

Exterior-collective holons (social)

1. Galaxies
2. Planets
3. Gaia system
4. Heterotrophic ecosystems
5. Societies with division of labor
6. Groups/families
7. Tribes (foraging)
8. Tribal/village (horticulture)
9. Early state/empire (agrarian)
10. Nation/state (industrial)
11. Planetary (informational)


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 198):

Interior-individual holons (intentional)

1. Prehension
2. Irritability
3. Sensation
4. Perception
5. Impulse
6. Emotion
7. Symbols
8. Concepts
9. Concrete operations
10. Formal operations
11. Vision-logic


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 198):

Interior-collective holons (cultural)

1. Physical-pleromatic
2. Protoplasmic
3. Vegetative
4. Locomotive
5. Uroboic
6. Typhonic
7. Archaic
8. Magic
9. Mythic
10. Rational
11. Centauric


Fenzl, Norbert et al. (1996, 275):

Systems

1. Physical and chemical (dissipative)
2. Biotic (autopoietic)
3. Socio-cultural (re-creational)


Mithen, Steven (1996, 69):

Mind

1. General intelligence
2. General intelligence supplemented by isolated multiple specialized intelligences
3. General intelligence supplemented by connected multiple specialized intelligences


Parker, Sue T. and Russon, Anne E. (1996, 438):

Culture and cognition

1. Preculture (e.g., social mammals, monkeys)
2. Protoculture (e.g., chimpaneezes)
3. Ur-culture (e.g., Middle Pleistocene hominids)
4. Eu-culture (modern humans)


Pettersson, Max (Pettersson 1996):

Entities

1. Fundamental particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. One-chromosome cells, and other intermediate entities
5. Cells with nuclei
6. Multicellular organisms
7. One-mother family societies, etc.
8. Multifamily society
9. Society of sovereign states


Deacon, Terrance (1997, 449):

Consciousness

1. Iconic representation
2. Indexical representation
3. Symbolic representation


Emmeche, Claus; Køppe, Simo and Frederick Stjernfelt (1997, 112–13):

Phenomena

1. Physical
2. Biological
3. Psycho-social


Damerow, Peter (1998, 10):

Prehistoric cognition

1. Sensorimotor or practical intelligence
2. Preoperational or symbolic intelligence (Middle to Upper Paleolithic transition)
3. Operational or reflective intelligence (e.g., urban revolution)


Commons, Michael L. et al. (1998, 247):

Tasks

1. Computory
2. Sensory and motor
3. Circular sensory-motor
4. Sensory-motor
5. Nominal
6. Sentential
7. Preoperational
8. Primary
9. Concrete
10. Abstract
11. Formal
12. Systematic
13. Metasystematic
14. Paradigmatic
15. Cross-paradigmatic


Cook-Greuter, Susanne R. ([1999] 2010, 197–203):

Ego

1. Symbiotic
2. Impulsive
3. Self-protective
4. Rule-oriented
5. Conformist
6. Self-aware
7. Conscientious
8. Individualist
9. Autonomous
10. Construct-aware
11. Unitive


Greenberg, Gary et al. (1999, 177):

Language and culture

1. Simple communication (monkey social group, low neocortical ratio)
2. Proto-language use (ape social group, intermediate neocortical ratio)
3. Language use (human culture, high neocortical ratio)


Donald, Merlin (2001, 260):

Cognition and culture

1. Episodic (primate)
2. Mimetic (early hominids, peaking in Homo erectus)
3. Mythic (sapient humans, peaking in Homo sapiens sapiens)
4. Theoretic (modern culture)


Donald, Merlin (2001, 325):

Conscious capacity

1. Pre-conscious (very simple perceptual objects, automatically bound, transient)
2. Level-1 basic (simple perceptual events, integrated across time but ephemeral)
3. Level-2 basic (complex events that can be held in short-term memory briefly)
4. Level-3 basic (complex social world-models held in extended working memory)
5. 1st-order hybrid (shared mimetic world-models that incorporate the physical self)
6. 2nd-order hybrid (shared narrative world-models, autobiographical self-awareness)
7. 3rd-order hybrid (shared theoretical world-models, external symbolic networks)


Brier, Søren (2003, 88, 96):

Matter and qualia

1. Quantum vacuum fields (Peirce's Firstness)
2. Physical (Peirce's Secondness)
3. Informational-chemical (Peirce's Thirdness)
4. Biological-semiotic (sign games)
5. Social-linguistic (language games)


Bunge, Mario (2003, 147):

Material things

1. Physical
2. Chemical
3. Biological
4. Social
5. Technical


Torbert, Bill et al. (2004, 126–27):

Action-logics

1. Impulsive (conception)
2. Opportunist (investment)
3. Diplomat (incorporation)
4. Expert (experiment)
5. Achiever (systematic)
6. Individualist (social network)
7. Strategist (collaborative inquiry)
8. Alchemist (foundational community of inquiry)


Bates, Marcia J. (2005, 13):

Information

1. Physical (information 1)
2. Biological (information 2)
3. Anthropological (knowledge)


Vickery, Brian (2005, no paging):

Material organization

1. Elementary particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Cells
5. Animals
6. Humans


Overton, Willis F. (2006, 20):

Discourse

1. Observational (common sense)
2. Theoretical (reflective)
3. Metatheoretical (metatheories)
4. Metatheoretical (ontological-epistemological groundings)


Overton, Willis F. (2006, 23):

Psychological subject

1. Practical (action systems)
2. Symbolic (representational action systems)
3. Reflective (2nd order representational action systems)
4. Trans-reflective (3rd order representational systems)


Dahlberg, Ingetraut (2008, 163):

Objects

1. General forms and structures
2. Matter and energy
3. Aggregated matter (cosmos and earth)
4. Biological objects (micro-organisms, plants, animals)
5. Human beings
6. Societal beings
7. Material products of mankind (products of economy and technology)
8. Intellectual products (scientific, information and communication products)
9. Spiritual products (language, literature, music, arts, etc.)


Lobo, Ingrid (2008, 141):

Biological matter

1. Macromolecule
2. Cell
3. Tissue
4. Organ and organ systems
5. Organism
6. Population
7. Communities and ecosystems
8. Biosphere


Pisula, Wojciech (2009, 123):

Exploratory behavior

1. Taxis
2. Orienting response
3. Locomotor exploration
4. Perceptual exploration
5. Investigatory responses
6. Cognitive curiosity


Salthe, Stanley (2009, 89):

Physical world

1. Physical dynamics
2. Material connectivity
3. Biological form
4. Social organization


Salthe, Stanley (2009, 97):

Physical entropy

1. Entropy production
2. Free energy expenditure
3. Metabolism
4. Cognition


Yao, Yiyu (2009, 1):

Information-processing

1. Numeric
2. Larger information granules
3. Symbol-based


Feinberg, Todd (2011, 4):

Neural self system

1. Interoself
2. Integrative
3. Exterosensorimotor


Feinberg, Todd (2011, 14):

Consciousness

1. Consciousness
2. Self
3. Self awareness


Tomasello, Michael (2014, 140):

Thinking

1. Individual intentionality (nonhuman great apes)
2. Joint intentionality (genus Homo, culminating in Homo heidelbergensis)
3. Collective intentionality (modern humans)


Nolan, Patrick and Lenski, Gerhard (2015, 6):

Things

1. Subatomic particles
2. Atoms
3. Molecules
4. Cells
5. Multicellular organisms
6. Societies
7. Species
8. Ecological communities
9. The global ecosystem


Nolan, Patrick and Lenski, Gerhard (2015, 64):

Societies

1. Hunting and gathering
2. Horticultural
3. Agrarian
4. Industrial


Gnoli, Claudio (2017, 46):

Phenomena

1. Forms
2. Matter
3. Life
4. Mind
5. Society
6. Culture

[top of entry]

Appendix B: Sample of conceptions of integrative levels

(Quotations are in chronological order of original publication. References marked with * use explicitly the terms "integrative levels" or "levels of integration.")


Comte, Auguste ([1830-1842] 1974, 52–53):

What we wish to find out is the real relationship of the various scientific studies. And that relationship can only be derived from the phenomena. Considering from this point of view all observable phenomena, we find we can divide them into a small number of categories, arranged so that the study of each category is founded on a knowledge of the principal laws of the preceding one, and is the foundation for the study of the following one. The order is determined by the degree of simplicity, or what amounts to the same thing, of generality in the phenomena, resulting in successive dependencies, and consequently greater or less difficulty in study. A priori we can decide that the most simple phenomena, those least complicated by others, are necessarily the most general.


Spencer, Herbert ([1860-1862] 1915, 321):

Evolution is an integration of matter and concomitant dissipation of motion; during which the matter passes from an indefinite, incoherent homogeneity to a definite, coherent heterogeneity; and during which the retained motion undergoes a parallel transformation.


Conger, George P. (1925, 315–16):

We may regard it as commonly agreed upon that the process of evolution is marked by the integration of individuated units of a lower level, let us say n, into individuated units of a higher level, let us say n+1. Integration is, however, by no means the only process which is going on; each individual unit at its own level  maintains itself by interactions with other units at level n, and with units of levels n-1, n-2, etc. Atoms, for example, are not merely integrated into molecules, but at their own level take on or give off electrons, and absorb and radiate energy.


Whitehead, Alfred N. ([1929] 1978, 21):

The ultimate metaphysical principle is the advance from disjunction to conjunction, creating a novel entity other than the entities given in disjunction. The novel entity is at once the togetherness of the 'many' which it finds, and also it is one among the disjunctive 'many' which it leaves; it is a novel entity, disjunctively among the many entities which it synthesizes. The many become one, and are increased by one. In their natures, entities are disjunctively 'many' in process of passage into conjunctive unity.


Needham, Joseph (1937, 3–4)*:

The theme of integrative levels is not one which we can approach without considerable hesitation, since the field which it covers is so wide and deep, no less than the whole nature of the world we know, and the way in which it has come into being. [...] The subject, then, to which our attention is to be given is the existence of levels of organization in the universe, successive forms of order in a scale of complexity and organization. [...] A sharp change in organizational level often means that what were wholes on the lower level become parts on the new [...].


Novikoff, Alex (1945, 209)*:

The concept of integrative levels of organization is a general description of the evolution of matter through successive and higher orders of complexity and integration.


Feibleman, James K. (1954, 59–64 [excerpted])*:

Some Laws of the Levels
1. Each level organises the level or levels below it plus one emergent quality.
2. Complexity of the levels increases upward.
3. In any organisation the higher level depends upon the lower.
4. In any organisation, the lower level is directed by the higher.
5. For an organisation at any given level, its mechanism lies at the level below and its purpose at the level above.
6. A disturbance introduced into an organisation at any one level reverberates at all the levels it covers.
7. The time required for a change in organisation shortens as we ascend the levels.
8. The higher the level, the smaller its population of instances.
9. It is impossible to reduce the higher level to the lower.
10. An organisation at any level is a distortion of the level below.
11. Events at any given level affect organisations at other levels.
12. Whatever is affected as an organisation has some effect as an organisation.

Rules of Explanation

1. The reference of any organisation must be at the lowest level which will provide sufficient explanation.
2. The reference of any organisation must be to the highest level which its explanation requires.
3. An organisation belongs to the highest level.
4. Every organisation must be explained finally on its own level.
5. No organisation can be explained entirely in terms of a lower or higher level.


Rowe, J. Stan (1961, 421)*:

We are now ready to state the basic proposition for a logical, useful level-of-integration scheme: The object of study of whatever level must contain, volumetrically or structurally, the objects of the lower levels, and must therefore be itself a part of the levels above. Each object will then constitute the immediate environment of the object at the level below while forming a structural-functional part of the object at the level above.


Koestler, Arthur (1967, 47–48 [emphasis his]):

The first universal characteristic of hierarchies is the relativity, and indeed ambiguity, of the terms 'part' and 'whole' when applied to any of the sub-assemblies. [...] A 'part', as we generally use the word, means something fragmentary and incomplete, which by itself would have no legitimate existence. On the other hand, a 'whole' is considered as something complete in itself which needs no further explanation. But 'wholes' and 'parts' in this absolute sense just do not exist anywhere, either in the domain of living organisms or of social organisations. What we find are intermediary structures on a series of levels in an ascending order of complexity: sub-wholes which display, according to the way you look at them, some of the characteristics commonly attributed to wholes and some of the characteristics commonly attributed to parts. [...] The term I would propose is 'holon', from Greek holos = whole, with the suffix on which, as in proton or neutron, suggests a particle or part.


Bertalanffy, Ludwig von (1968, 86):

Reality, in the modern conception, appears as a tremendous hierarchical order of organized entities, leading, in a superposition of many levels, from physical and chemical to biological and sociological systems. Unity of Science is granted, not by a utopian reduction of all sciences to physics and chemistry, but by the structural uniformities of the different levels of reality.


Austin, Derek (1969a, 156)*:

It is well known that CRG [Classification Research Group, M.K.] have for some time been investigating the order suggested by Integrative Levels Theory. This states that every material entity can be assigned to a level according to its structure, so that, for example, the integration of elementary particles leads to a new and higher level, the element, which possesses new and different properties. Elements in their turn become compounds, then minerals, rocks and so on. This approach has now been supplemented by two more general principles, that is, the principle of consecutiveness, and causal dependence.


Jolley, John L. (1973, 111)*:

These observations lead us to a rule which may be helpful: ideas are to be placed after those which form them and before those which they form. A brief examination of the textbooks then produces a sequence of the following sort: particles — atoms — molecules — organelles — cells — organs of the body — people — communities — nations. [...] These pioneers have given the name 'integrative levels' to the degree of complexity in the build-up of the world.


Foskett, Douglas J. (1978, 204)*:

To put is rather simply, the theory of integrative levels is that the world of entities evolves from the simple towards the complex by an accumulation of properties or incluences from the environments.


Aronson, Lester R. (1987, 269)*:

Numerous hierarchies have been described, and among these descriptions, belongs a particular view, nameley, levels of organization and integration, the so-called 'levels concept.' A distinguishing feature of this concept is its grounding in evolutionary theory and emphasis on the importance of the element of time. It emphasizes continuity in that both the inorganic and organic world are continually changing with a strong trend towards greater complexity in organization and integration. The accumulation of small, quantitative changes leads to transformations into more complex and qualitatively different entities. [...] Levels are thus wholes and at the same time parts of wholes of the next higher level whose properties are now more complex and qualitatively different. In essence, the wholes of one level become parts of the higher one with its unique properties of form and function.


Tobach, Ethel (1987, 242, 244)*:

Primarily, the concept of integrative levels is based on the notion that change is an inherent characteristic of matter that is evident throughout the universe and all its parts. A corollary of this concept is that any phenomenon, structural or functional, must have a history. [...] Each discontinuity may represent a new level of organization and integration, if it can be demonstrated that the preceding level had characteristics that make it possible for a new structural/functional organization to develop. The new level, or the discontinuity, contains within itself some characteristics of the preceding level to produce a continuity with the preceding level.


Campbell, Donald T. (1990, 4)*:

1. All processes at the higher level are restrained by and act in conformity to laws of the lower levels, including the levels of subatomic physics (a 'reductionist' contrain). 2. The telenomic achievements at higher levels require for their implementation specific lower level mechanisms and processes. Explanation is not complete until these micromechanisms have been specified (a 'reductionist' contrain). 3. (The emergentist principle) Biological evolution, in its meandering exploration of segments of the universe, encouters laws, operating as selective systems, which are not described by the present laws of physics and inorganic chemistry, and which will not be described by the future substitutes for the present approximations. 4. (Downward causation) Where natural selection operates through life and death at a higher level of organization, the laws of the higher level selective system determine in part the distribution of lower level events and substances.


Salthe, Stanley N. (1991, 25, emphases his)*:

[T]he specification hierarchy [...] can be represented as a system of nested classes, the outermost class containing the most general phenomena, the innermost the most highly specified. These integrative levels can be considered as stages of development as well. Each new stage transcends the one before it and integrates it into a new whole.


Vromann, Leo (1995, 417, emphasis his)*:

A level is an observable interruption of a continuity. A level of integration is a level where several entities (e.g., objects that can be defined and named) jointly have reached integration to such a degree that they are forming a new entity.


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 43–81 [excerpted]):

1. Reality as a whole is not composed of things or processes, but of holons.
2. Holons display four fundamental capacities: self-preservation, self-adaptation, self-transcendence, and self-dissolution.
3. Holons emerge.
4. Holons ermerge holarchically.
5. Each emergent holon transcends but includes its predecessor(s).
6. The lower sets the possibilities of the higher; the higher sets the probabilities of the lower.
7. "The number of levels which a hierarchy comprises determines wether it is shallow or deep; and the number of holons on any given level we shall call its 'span'." [quotation from Arthur Koestler]
8. Each successive level of evolution produces GREATER depth and LESS span. [...] Addition 1: The greater the depth of a holon, the greater its degree of consciousness.
9. Destroy any type of holon, and you will destroy all of the holons above it and none of the holons below it.
10. Holarchies coevolve.
11. The micro is in relational exchange with the macro at all levels of its depth.
12. Evolution has directionality.

a) Increasing complexity.
b) Increasing differentiation/integration.
c) Increasing organization/structuration.
d) Increasing relative autonomy.
e) Increasing telos.


Fenzl, Norbert et al. (1996, 273, 275; emphases his):

Reality thus has a diachronic and synchronic character, it is behaviour and structure, which run into each other and influence each other. The dynamic side is expressed in a dialectic of old and new, the static in a dialectic of whole and part, which together constitute the evolutionary context: the new originates as part of the old whole and continues up to a specific point [...]. [...] today's universe with all its subsystems seem to be the product of a chain of self-organization cycles, contained one within the other.


Pettersson, Max (1996, 12, emphases his)*:

It has become clear to me that there are two main criteria by which the nine major integrative levels have come to be discerned and discriminated: (1) By the compositional criterion, it is a requirement that each entity of any major integrative level (except the lowest) materially consists mainly of entities of the next lower level. (2) By the duality criterion, it is a requirement that some of the entities of any major integrative level (except the highest) are joined, bonded or fused together with others, with which they collaborate in the constitution of an entity of the next higher level, while some other entities of the same major integrative level exist as free and independent entities."


Emmeche, Claus; Køppe, Simo and Stjernfelt, Frederik (1997, 93, emphasis theirs):

Levels are inclusive in that respect, i.e. the psychological level is built upon the biological and the physical, the biological upon the physical. Phenomena on one level cannot be reduced to the lower level, but on the other hand they can never change the laws of the lower level. Biological phenomena cannot change physical laws, – but neither can physical laws as we known them fully explain biological phenomena. The fact that levels are inclusive mean that a lower is a necessary condition for the higher level, and that the higher level supervenes upon the lower.


Lobo, Ingrid (2008, 141)*:

[U]nits of matter are organized and integrated into levels of increasing complexity; this is a concept referred to as integrative levels of organization. Integrative levels of organization allow researchers to describe the evolution from the inanimate to the animate and social worlds. Higher integrative levels are more complex and demonstrate more variation and characteristics than lower integrative levels. These levels are based upon a physical foundation, with the lowest level appearing to consist of subatomic particles.


Pisula, Wojciech (2009, 32)*:

The problem of control, from a comparative perspective seems to be a relative one. Depending on what we are looking at, a given level of the process may be controlled by the higher one. At the same time the given level may be controlling something else which is running at the lower levels of organization. The paradigm of the theory of integrative levels seems to be most appropriate for this problem. There is a primary advantage of the approach based on the theory of intgerative levels. It is, that different forms of behavior may be treated as instances of the same fundamental phenomenon seen at different levels of the continuous process of integration.


Yoa, Yiyu (2009, 42)*:

The notion of granularity is introduced to interpret the concept of integrative levels, and thus we have the notion of integrative levels of granularity. Each level is populated with granules of similar size or of similar nature. The levels of granularity may be interpreted as the levels of organization, levels of control, levels of complexity, levels of understanding, levels of description, levels of representation, levels of interpretation, levels of abstraction, levels of details, levels of processing and so on. The universality of levels implies that integrative levels of granularity may be used as a basis for granular computing. [...] With integrative levels of granularity, we consider granular structures that represent both multiple levels and multiple views. A single hierarchy gives one multilevel view of reality; many hierarchies give a multiview description of reality.

[top of entry]

Appendix C: Sample of conceptions of integrative levels of knowing

(Quotations are in chronological order of original publication.)


Comte, Auguste ([1830-1842] 1974, 20):

This law is that each of our principal conceptions, each branch of our knowledge, passes successively through three different theoretical stages: the theological or fictitous, the metaphysical or abstract, and the scientific or positive. In other words, the human mind, by its nature, employs in all its investigations three methods of philosophising, of an essientially different and even opposed nature: first the theological, then the metaphysical, and finally the positive.


Spencer, Herbert (1873, 491):

I need hardly say that this evolution of composite feelings through the progressive integration of psychical states are connected in experience, is effected by the inheritance of continually-accumulating modifications. The law of development of the mental activities considered under their cognitive aspect, equally applies to them considered under their emotional aspect.


Hobhouse, Leonard T. (1901, 373):

If we accept evolution, analogy suggests that human intelligence is a specific and higher development of a more general form of intelligence. Hence, if we cut away the higher development, we should come to something roughly common to man and the higher animals. If we cut further away, we should come to something common to man and a wider class of animals, and so forth.


Dilthey, Wilhelm ([1910] 2002, 149; emphasis his):

Knowlegde constitues a hierarchy of functions: the given is explicated in elementary logical functions, it is reproduced in mental representations, and it is logically represented in discursive thought — the given is thus subjected to various kinds of re-presentation. The explication of the given through elementary logical operations, its reproduction in the remembered representation, and its being logically represented in discursive thought can all be subsumed under the encompassing concept of re-presentation.


Wundt, Wilhelm ([1912] 1916, 513):

Thus, that which is in a high degree characteristic of world religion is true also of world history. Within the conscious horizon of each individual very different levels of historical consciousness are represented, even in the case of the cultural peoples who participate more or less actively in the course of world history. Here, as in world religion, we find that what was developed in a sequence during the course of ages continues to remain, at any rate roughly speaking, in juxtaposition.


Cassirer, Ernst ([1923] 1955, 303):

For epistemological inquiry an unbroken path leads from sensation to intuition, from intuition to conceptual thought, and thence to logical judgment. Yet in following this path, the epistemologist is aware that sharply as its phases must be distinguished in reflection, they must never be regarded as independent data of consciousness, existing separately from one another. On the contrary, every more complex factor here includes the simpler ones, and every 'later' one the 'earlier', while conversely the latter contains within it the seeds of the former.


Morgan, Conwy Lloyd (1923, 17):

The evolutionary genesis of contemplative thought involves that which has already been developed at the lower level of naive perception; and the genesis of such perception involves, as historically prior, sensory presentation.


Mannheim, Karl ([1924/25] 1982, 264):

Although the encroaching civilizational way of knowing increasingly drives these mythical and magical elements out of everyday practical knowledge, mythical and magical components do nevertheless survive in our everyday knowledge of life even today. [...] The consciousness of the individual, then, may be likened to a petrification of past ages in the history of consciousness, and just as geology can reconstruct the history of the earth' crust, so the career of consciousness is preserved in stratified layers in the make-up of the individual consciousness of the present.


Vygotsky, Lev S. ([1934] 1986, 140):

It would be erroreous, however, to imagine that this transition from complexes to concepts is a mechanical process in which the higher developmental stage completely supersedes the lower one. The developmental scene turns out to be much more complex. Different genetic forms coexist in thinking, just as different rock formations coexists in the earth's crust."


Needham, Joseph (1937, 49):

Every transition from the unconscious to the conscious implies a step from bondage to freedom, from lower to higher level of organization. All early agriculture and storage of food-products necessitated more conscious control than before. Increases in the efficiency of mechanisms of transport from horse to the aeroplane widened men's conscious horizon.


Bachelard, Gaston ([1940] 1968, 17):

There is no end to the dispute about moral progress, social progress, poetic progress or the progress of happiness, but there is one form of progress which is beyond argument and that is scientific progress, as soon as it comes to be judged in the hierarchy of knowledge and in its specifically intellectual aspects. We are therefore going to take the direction of this progress as the axis of our philosophic study and if, on the abscissa of its development, philosophical systems place themselves regularly in an order constant for all notions, an order which moves from animism to surrationalism (via realism, positivism and simple rationalism) we shall be somewhat justified in speaking of a philosophical progress of scientific notions.


Hartmann, Nicolai ([1942] 1953, 46):

Thereby consciousness liberates itself from subservience to vitality and becomes a spiritual consciousness. It thus enters into a certain contrast with that primary consciousness which is determined by instinctive life and harnessed to its service. The latter may be called 'spiritless consciousness.' It is not extinguished in the fully developed human being but persists in the background of his spiritual consciousness. Occasionally it may break forth all of a sudden, perverting the objective order of the spirit. In the young child this spiritless consciousness is the dominant one, just as it is in the higher animals, and there is little doubt that through long periods of man's prehistoric development his consciousness was predominantly a spiritless one.


Maslow, Abraham (1943, 370):

Human needs arrange themselves in hierarchies of pre-potency. That is to say, the appearance of one need usually rests on the prior satisfaction of another, more pre-potent need. Man is a perpetually wanting animal. Also no need or drive can be treated as if it were isolated or discrete; every drive is related to the state of satisfaction or dissatisfaction of other drives.


Gebser, Jean ([1949] 1985, 42; emphasis his):

In order to achieve the requisite basis for transformation to which we have alluded, we wish to present as a working hypothesis the four, respectively five, structures we have designated as the archaic, magical, mythical, mental, and integral. We must first of all remain cognizant that these structures are not merely past, but are in fact still present in more or less latent and acute form in each one of us.


Neumann, Erich ([1949] 1975, 264):

When we speak of stages of conscious development, we mean [...] the archetypal stages, though at the same time we have repeatedly stressed their evolutionary and historical character. These stages, with their fluctuating degrees of ego consciousness, can be shown to be archetypal; that is, they work as an 'eternal presence' in the psyche of modern man and form elements of his psychic structure.


Piaget, Jean ([1955] 1977, 815; emphasis his):

The integrative character of stages: the structures constructed at a given age become an integral part of the structures of the following age. For example, the permanent object that is constructed at the sensorimotor level will be an integral element in notions of conservation formed later (when there will be conservation of an ensemble, or of a collection, or of an object undergoing deformation in its spatial appearance). In the same way, the operations that we call concrete will constitute an integral part of formal operation, in the sense that the latter will constitute a new structure but resting on the former, which are thus treated as their contents (formal operations thus constituting operations effectuated upon other operations).


Steward, Julian H. ([1955] 1972, 51):

The utility of distinguishing levels of sociocultural integration as well as categories of phenomena can be strikingly illustrated in studies of cultural change and acculturation. In the growth continuum of any culture, there is a succession of organizational types which are not only increasingly complex but which represent new emergent forms. The concept is fairly similar to that of organizational levels in biology. In culture, simple forms, such as those represented by the family or band, do not wholly disappear when a more complex stage of development is reached, nor do they merely survive fossil-like, as the concepts of folkways and mores formely assumed. They gradually become modified as specialized, dependent parts of new kinds of total configurations.


Werner, Heinz and Kaplan, Bernard (1956, 866):

The developmental psychology of cognition postulates one regulative principle of development, the following orthogenetic principle: whereever development occurs, it proceeds from a state of relative lack of differentiation to a state of increasing differentiation, articulation, and hierarchic integration.


Erikson, Erik H. ([1959] 1980, 125; emphases his):

From a genetic point of view, then, the process of identity formation emerges as an evolving configuration — a configuration which is gradually established by successive ego syntheses and resyntheses throughout childhood; it is a configuration gradually integrating constitutional givens, idiosyncratic libidinal needs, favored capacities, significant identifications, effective defenses, successful sublimations, and consistent roles.


Sahlin, Marshall D. and Service, Elman R. ([1960] 1988, 35–36):

As in life, thermodynamic achievement has its organizational counterpart, higher levels of integration. Cultures that transform more energy have more parts and subsystems, more specializations of parts, and more effective means of integration of the whole. Organizational symptoms of general progress include the proliferation of material elements, geographic increase in the division of labor, multiplication of social groups and subgroups, and the emergence of special means of integration: political, such as chieftainship and the state, and philosophical, such as universal ethical religions and science.


Perry, William G. (1968, 2):

A person moving from the assumptions of student A to those of student B to those of student C may therefore be said to be involved in a development, not simply because his assumptions become 'better' or more 'true' — which is another question — but because the forms of his later assumptions subtend those of his earlier assumptions in a coherent manner, as cannot be said in reverse.


Graves, Clare W. (1970, 133):

I am proposing: the psychology of the mature human being is an unfolding or emergent process marked by the progressive subordination of older behavioral systems to newer, higher order behavior systems. The mature man tends normally to change his psychology as the conditions of his existence change. Each successive stage or level is a state of equilibrium through which people pass on the way to other states of equilibrium. When a person is in one of the states of equilibrium, he has a psychology which is particular to that state. His acts, feelings, motivations, ethics and values, thoughts and preferences for management are all appropriate to that state.


Lorenz, Konrad ([1973] 1977, 245):

There are in my view definite signs that a self-recognition of all cultural humanity, a collective self-knowledge derived from natural science, is beginning to spring up. If, as is entirely possible, this movement grows, the intellectual aspirations and energies of mankind will be raised to a higher level of integration, as in the distant past the 'creative flash' or reflection and meditation raised man's power of understanding to a new and higher level.


Luria, Alexander R. ([1974] 1976, 161–62):

Our investigations, which were conducted under unique and non-replicable conditions involving a transition to collectivized forms of labor and cultural revolution, showed that, as the basic forms of activity change, as literacy is mastered, and a new stage of social and historical practice is reached, major shifts occur in human mental activity. These are not limited simply to an expanding of man's horizons, but involve the creation of new motives for action and radically affect the structure of cognitive processes. [...] In addition to elementary graphic-functional motives, we see the creation of new motives that take shape in the process of collectivized labor, the joint planning of labor activity, and basic schooling.


Habermas, Jürgen ([1976] 1979, 184–85; emphases his):

Thus, by levels of justification I mean formal conditions for the acceptability of grounds or reasons, conditions that lend to legitimations their efficacy, their power to produce consensus and shape motives. These levels can be ordered hierarchically. The legitimations of a superseded stage, no matter what their content, are depreciated with the transition to the next higher stage; it is not this or that reason which is no longer convincing but the kind of reason. Such depreciation of the legitimation potential of entire blocks of tradition occurred in civilizations with the retrenchment of mythological thought, and in modern times with the retrenchment of cosmological, religious, and ontological modes of thought.


Kohlberg, Lawrence and Hersh, Richard H. (1977, 54; ehmpases theirs):

1. Stages are 'structured wholes,' or organized systems of thought. This means individuals are consistent in their level of moral judgment. 2. Stages form an invariant sequence. Under all conditions except extreme trauma, movement is always forward, never backward. Individuals never skip stages, and movement is always to the next stage up. This is true in all cultures. 3. Stages are 'hierarchical integrations.' Thinking at a higher stage includes or comprehends within it lower stage thinking. There is a tendency to function at or prefer the highest stage available.


Leontiev, Aleksei N. ([1977] 2009, 190–91):

If, in the initial steps of the child's psychological development, his biological adaptations (which make a decisive contribution to establishing his perceptions and emotions) appear at the first plane, then subsequently these adaptations are transformed. This of course does not mean that they simply stop functioning; it means something else, specifically that they begin to realize another higher level of activity on which the amount they contribute at each given stage of development depends.


Apel, Karl-Otto (1978, 10):

Thus my conception of a revolutionary succession of different paradigms of thought differs from that of Th. Kuhn in that it implies some sort of a Hegelian idea of possible progress in the history of human thought. Properly speaking, it does not imply any claim of a causally explicable and hence predictable necessity of progress. Rather, it implies the claim that the three paradigms of First Philosophy make up a hierarchical order of levels of critical reflection and also make up an order of necessary succession in the teleological sense without providing any guarantee of its being realized in advance of the facts of history.


Gablik, Suzi (1979, 71):

The fact that all these levels are conserved at the same time as they are superseded is what gives history its integrative character and its continuity. A content that has been used on one level with respect to a certain kind of structure can be transposed onto another, by being reconstructed in a new way of thinking. The resulting pattern appears as a succession of repeated differentiations, specializations and reintegrations, with a distinct progression from simple intuition to more complex logical and rational structures.


Jantsch, Erich ([1979] 1980, 296):

The conclusion may be drawn that it is not individual levels which impart depth or height (both terms seem to express the same notion here!), but the multilevel vibrations of many levels of consciousness. A new level does not mean an 'ascent' but an enrichment of the ensemble of possibilities of expression and the dimensions of its autonomy.


Fischer, Kurt (1980, 485):

The skills at each level are characterized by a structure that indicates the kinds of behaviors that the person can control at that level. Also, at each level, the skills include all the lower levels.


Selman, Robert L. (1980, 36):

We tried to construct the levels such that they both described and were defined by genuine universal development in both the hierarchical sense, in which higher levels are built on lower ones, and the structural or reorganizational sense, in which at each higher level a new operational principle takes command.


Fowler, James W. (1981, 99–100):

Moreover, we believe that faith stages meet the structural-developmental criteria for stages. They provide generalizable, formal descriptions of integrated sets of operations of knowing and valuing. These stagelike positions are related in a sequence we believe to be invariant. Each new stage integrates and carries forward the operations of all the previous stages.


Kegan, Robert (1982, 85; quoted without references):

It has been called a process of decentration, emergence from embeddedness, the recurring triumph over egocentrism; it has been referred to as a process in which the whole becomes a part to a new whole; in which what was structure becomes content on behalf of a new structure; in which what was ultimate becomes preliminary on behalf of a new ultimacy; in which what was immediate gets mediate to a new immediacy. All these descriptions speak to the same process, which is essentially that of adaptation, a differentiation from that which was the very subject of my personal organization and which becomes thereby the object of a new organization on behalf of a new subjectivity that coordinates it.


Turiel, Elliot (1983, 19):

Development is continually directed toward increasing equilibrium, so that each stage is a more equilibrated state than the previous one. Equilibrium, however, does not simply mean adjustment of conformity to external pressures. There are two interrelated aspects to structural equlilibrium. One refers to the equlilibrium or coherence of a system of thinking. The second refers to an understanding of the environment in the most powerful, comprehensive, and effective way. That is, each stage of development represents a more equilibrated means of understanding the environment than the previous stage.


Stern, Daniel N. ([1985] 2006, 32):

In fact, each successive organizing subjective perspective requires the preceding one as a precursor. Once formed, the domains remain forever as distinct forms of experiencing social life and self. None are lost to adult experience. Each simply gets more elaborated.


Campbell, Robert L. and Bickhard, Mark H. (1986, XI–XII):

The potentialities of properties which may implicitly present at one level of knowing becoming explicitly known from the next higher level iterates unboundedly, generating the primary knowing levels hierarchy. This hierarchy, in turn, generates the corresponding knowing levels developmental stage model: no system at a given knowing level can be constructed, can develop, unless there are already existing systems at all lower knowing levels supporting it. Development through the knowing levels, then, must proceed in a strict stage sequence.


Parsons, Michael J. (1987, 20–21):

There are two ways in which one may think of a stage as being more adequate than the previous one. The first is aesthetic. Each stage understands paintings more adequately than before. The account of changing understandings of each topic is therefore also an account of their increasing adequacy, stage by stage. [...] The second kind of adequacy is psychological. The stages rest on our increasing ability to take the perspective of others, the common dimension of cognitive developmental schemes.


Damon, William and Hart, Daniel (1988, 57–58):

It is important to note that, in a hierarchical model such as this one, the earlier levels become part of the later ones, though in somewhat new form. Thus, for example, self-understanding of the 'me' is always categorical, as at Level 1; but later levels employ the categorical mode for new purposes. Thus, earlier forms of self-understanding neither disappear nor are retained per se. Rather they continue to function in transformed state as part of later forms.


Kramer, Deidre A. (1989, 56–57):

The major principle of cognitive change in the present model is that of the orthogenetic principle, that is, that all development proceeds from a state of relative undifferentiation toward that of differentiation, and finally hierarchical integration. [...] Such a model allows for a unified conception of life-span development, where thought is reconstructed at each level, with each new level providing greater inclusivness and (at the integrated level) coherence than the previous level.


LePan, Don (1989, 20–21):

Once again, what distinguishes the characteristic mode of thought of modern developed societies from those of primitive societies is not the absence of primitive processes in the Western mind, but the presence of additional modes of causal, temporal and logical thought.


King, Patricia M. and Kitchener, Karen S. (1994, 13):

This develomental progression in reasoning is described by seven distinct sets of assumptions about knowledge and how knowledge is aquired. Each set of assumptions has its own logical coherency and is called a stage. Each successive stage is posited to represent a more complex and effective form of justification, providing more inclusive and better integrated assumptions for evaluating and defending a point of view.


Wilber, Ken ([1995] 2000, 118–19):

The important point, for now, is simply that each new and emergent interior holon transcends but includes, and thus operates upon, the information presented by its junior holons, and thus it fashions something novel in the ongoing cognitive or interior stream. Hence, each new growth in consciousness is not just a 'discovery' of more of a pregiven world, but the co-creation of new worlds themselves, what Popper calls a 'making and matching' of new epistemological domains, a discovery/creation of higher and wider worlds.


Deacon, Terrance (1997, 449):

If consciousness is inevitably representational, then it follows that a change in the nature of the way information gets represented inevitably constitutes a change in consciousness. Consciousness of iconic representations should differ from consciousness of indexical representations, and this in turn should differ from consciousness of symbolic representations. Moreover, since these modes of representation are not alternatives at the same level but hierarchically and componentially related to one another, this must also be true of these modes of consciousness as well. They form a nested hierarchy, where certain conditions in the lower levels of consciousness are prerequisite to the emergence of consciousness at each higher level.


Egan, Kieran (1997, 4):

My primary aim in this book is to unravel some of the major strands or layers of our typically polysemous understanding. I try to separate out a set of general and distinctive kinds of understanding and characterize each of them in detail; I distinguish five, which I call Somatic, Mythic, Romantic, Philosophic, and Ironic. I try to show, furthermore, that these kinds of understanding have developed in evolution and cultural history in a particular sequence, coalescing to a large extent (but not completely) as each successive kind has emerged. The modern mind thus is represented as a composite.


Commons, Michael et al. (1998, 240; emphases theirs):

The General Model of Hierarchical Complexity uses the hierarchical complexity of tasks as the basis for the definition of stage. An action is at a given stage when it successfully completes a task of a given hierarchical order of complexity. Roughly, hierarchical complexity refers to the number of nonrepeating recursions that the coordinating actions must perform on a set of primary elements. Actions at a higher order of hierarchical complexity: (a) are defined in terms of the actions at the next lower order of hierarchical complexity; (b) organize and transform the lower order actions; (c) produce organizations of lower order actions that are new and not arbitrary and cannot be accomplished by those lower order actions alone.


Loevinger, Jane (1998, 37):

A final line of evidence for sequentiality is asymmetry of comprehension, that is, people can understand thinking at their own level or at levels below their own, but not at levels above their own.


Cook-Greuter, Susanne R. ([1999] 2010, 19–20):

On the whole, developmental stage theories based on Piaget's ideas describe human development as a sequence of increasingly complex and integrated stages or coherent systems of meaning making. Each stage constitutes a different way of how people know reality, in other words, a different epistemology, or a different world-view. Central to this model is the claim that the stage sequence is unidirectional and that the stages constitute hierarchical integrations. [...] A new stage integrates the material or content of the previous one as a special case, that is, as an element into its more inclusive meaning system. Each stage is thus a part/whole. It is a whole in its own right, as well as part of a bigger, more expansive system of understanding.


Greenberg, Gary et al. (1999, 175):

Lower levels of organization and their functions are not 'replaced' by higher levels; rather, they are subsumed at the higher levels. They become integral parts of the new, more highly organized system. Lower functions are thus conserved at the higher levels. So it is expected that organisms at many levels of neural complexity will display simple stimulus-response learning capacities.


Barnes, Michael H. (2000, 45; emphases his):

Piaget's description of stages helps to categorize thought styles more clearly. His theory also helps to recognize the particular sequence in which stages of thought appear in cultural history. In cultures as in individuals, the easier modes of thought appear first and continue to be used even when more difficult modes of thought are added.


Dux, Günter ([2000] 2011, 118):

The more clearly the development of all history comes into view, the greater the contrasts that become evident between past societies and ours, the more urgent the question why people acted and thought in early societies differently from their counterparts in later societies, and why these later societies were able to develop out of earlier ones. [...] The most encompassing condition of development of each and every society, however, is the structure of the society that precedes it, out of which the new one has developed.


Kuhn, Thomas S. (2000, 227; emphasis his):

Concerned from the start with the development of knowledge, I have seen each stage in the evolution of a given field as built — not quite squarely — upon its predecessor, the earlier stage providing the problems, the data, and most of the concepts prerequisite to the emergence of the stage that followed.


Donald, Merlin (2001, 262):

Thus modern culture contains within it a trace of each of our previous stages of cognitive evolution. It still rests on the same old primate brain capacity for episodic or event knowledge. But it has three additional, uniquely human layers: a mimetic layer, an oral-linguistic layer, and an external-symbolic layer. The minds of individuals reflect these three ways of representing reality.


Torbert, William R. (2004, 68; emphasis theirs):

First, each successive action-logic we describe includes all the possibilities of the prior action-logics and a whole new set of alternatives as well. Thus, at each later action-logic we have more degrees of freedom about which action-logic we use when.


Overton, Willis F. (2006, 25–26):

All nonlinear dynamic systems, including the human psyche, undergo transformational change. Transformational change results in the emergence of novelty. As forms change, they become increasingly complex. This increased complexity is a complexity of pattern rather than a linear additive complexity of elements.


Hallpike, Christopher R. (2008, 123–24):

The human mind is not like an empty bucket that is gradually filled with information by adults, or by passively observing the world around one; each individual has actively to construct his understanding of the world, of things and of people, by interacting and experimenting with himself. [...] Some ways of thinking are more elementary than others, and provide the foundation on which the more advanced and complex types of thought can be constructed, when the social conditions are right.


Combs, Allan (2009, 89):

If we stand back and view the stages of growth charted there from infancy to adulthood, we see that one important theme that runs throughout development is a persistent increase in internal complexity which lies inside and powers the growth of the mind. This complexity presents itself in the form of increasingly sophisticated schemas and patterns of schemas all of which constitute a person's mind.


Esbjörn-Hargens, Sean and Zimmerman, Michael E. (2009, 145):

All shifts from one level of development to the next involve a crisis of the self. The self is letting go of old ways of interpreting and seeing the world. It is a death of an old self and a birth of a new, more inclusive self.


Bellah, Robert N. (2011, 117):

I offered a typology of religious representation — unitive, enactive, symbolic, and conceptual — to describe the way in which religions have understood reality. The concepts of enactive, symbolic, and conceptual representation were adapted from the work of Jerome Bruner on child development. [...] I argued that religion draws on all these forms of representation: just as the child continuous to use enactive and symbolic representations, even after becoming conceptually sophisticated, so do religions.


Mortimer, Eduardo F. et al. (2014, 23):

The development of new forms of activity gives rise to new types of thinking. Nevertheless, since earlier forms of activity continue to fulfill some role in culture, the old types of thinking employed in these earlier forms are preserved and continued to function well in their appropriate contexts.


Lourenço, Orlando M. (2016, 123, emphases his):

In a strong conception of development, developmental stages are characterized by the following criteria: (a) Hierarchy: stages appear in an invariant, hierarchical order; (b) integration: a given stage integrates, albeit overcomes or transcends its predecessor; (c) consolidation: before all features that define a certain stage are present, there is a phase of preparation wherein the stage still presents some features of the previous one; (d) structuration: a stage is organized by what Piaget called structures d'ensemble or overarching structures, that is, a way of thinking/knowing which has some formal and logical properties and is applied to different contents; and (e) equilibrium: if an individual is capable of performing according to the criteria of a given stage, then s/he is at a certain degree of (unstable) equilibrium, and is not cognitively 'perturbed' when s/he has to solve problems whose solution does not require competencies that go beyond the competences linked to the stage at hand.

[top of entry]

 

Visited Hit Counter by Digits times since 2019-11-20 (2 years and a half after first publication).


Version 1.2 (= 1.1 with "Pisula 2006" corrected to "2009"); published 2017-05-04, last edited 2020-02-19
Article category: Methods, approaches & philosophies

This article (version 1.0) is also published in Knowledge Organization. How to cite it:
Kleineberg, Michael. 2017. “Integrative levels”. Knowledge Organization 44, no. 5: 349-379. Also available in ISKO Encyclopedia of Knowledge Organization, eds. Birger Hjørland and Claudio Gnoli, https://www.isko.org/cyclo/integrative_levels

©2017 ISKO. All rights reserved.